Playing the Other: Theater, Theatricality, and the Feminine in Greek Drama
Author(s): Froma I. Zeitlin
Source:
Representations,
No. 11 (Summer, 1985), pp. 63-94
Published by: University of California Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2928427 .
Accessed: 16/01/2014 14:04
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
.
University of California Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Representations.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FROMA I.
ZEITLIN
Playing
the Other:
Theater,
Theatricality,
and the Feminine
in
Greek Drama
FOR
A SPECIMEN OF
SHEER theatrical
power,
it would be difficult
to match the climactic
scene of
Euripides'
Bacchae
(788-861)
where
Pentheus at
last comes under
the spell of his adversary,
the
god
Dionysus,
and
acknowledges
his secret desire
to spy upon
the women
of Thebes who have
left the
city
to
go
as maenads to
the mountain.
His violent
antagonism
toward
the women
who,
in
abandoning
their homes, children,
and domestic
tasks,
have
challenged
the
civic,
masculine
authority
of the
king gives
way
to a sudden
softening
of will-a
yielding
to the
cunning
wiles
of the
god
disguised
on
stage
as the Asiatic
stranger,
the
leader of his own
troops
of maenads.
This first surrender
is followed
by
another.
Giving up
now his
original
intention to marshal his forces for an
open
combat
of men
against
women,
Pentheus
gives
up
his stubborn
claim to an
unequivocal
masculine
identity.
To
see what the
women are
doing
without himself
being
seen,
Pentheus must
trade
his
hoplite
military tactics
for an undercover
operation
that
involves adopting
a devious stratagem
and
assuming
a remarkable
disguise.
He
must
let
the
god
take
him
inside
the
palace
and dress
him as
a woman
in
a
flowing
wig and headdress,
a
long pleated
robe and belt, to which
he adds
the
typical
insignia of the
maenads-the dappled
fawnskin and ritual
thyrsus. When
the
god completes
this elaborate toilette,
Pentheus will also resemble Dionysus
him-
self,
whose effeminate appearance
the king had earlier
mocked.' But as
much
as
they might
seem doublets
of
one
another,
the
power
relations between them
have been decisively
reversed. Now
Dionysus will turn
Pentheus from the
one
who
acts
to
the one
who is
acted upon,
from the one who would inflict pain
and
suffering,
even death,
on the
other,
to the
one who will undergo those experi-
ences himself. For
now, however,
the
preliminary sign
of Pentheus' total defeat,
first at
the hands
of
Dionysus and then
at the hands of
the women, is given
to
us on
stage
in
the visual feminization
of Pentheus when
he is induced against
all
inhibitions of shame
to adopt the costume
and gestures
of the woman.
But if feminization is the emblem of Pentheus' defeat,
Dionysus' effeminacy
is a
sign
of his
hidden power.
Here are two males, cousins
in
fact through their
genealogical ties,
both
engaged
in
a masculine contest for
supremacy. One,
how-
ever,
gains
mastery by manipulating
a
feminized identity
and the other is
van-
REPRESENTATIONS
11 *
Summer 1985
?
THE
REGENTS
OF THE
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA
63
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
quished when he finally
succumbs to it. What we
might perceive in their
ensemble
at the
moment when the
two males appear
together on stage in similar
dress is
an
instructive spectacle
of the inclusive functions
of the feminine in the
drama-
one on
the side of
femininity as power and the
other on the side of
femininity
as
weakness.
Pentheus, first
ashamed of wearing women's
clothing, and terrified
that he
make a ridiculous
spectacle
of
himself for all
the city to see, now has a
fleeting
intimation of the new
force he has acquired,
exulting in the surge of
unnatural
physical strength that
suffuses
him
and
dreaming of uprooting
mountains with
his bare hands. But
under the god's gentle
prodding, he just as eagerly
abandons
his desire for violence to
acquiesce with pleasure
in the contrary tactics of
hiding
and
deception
that
will confront the women
on
their own terms
(953-56). The
moment of
triumph and
confidence, however, is
brief.
We know already in
advance
what the fate of Pentheus will be
once the
feminized god Dionysus, who
plays his
role
to perfection, delivers over his
disguised
victim, his man clumsily
concealed
in
women's dress, to the
"real" women who will
tear the imposter
apart in a
terrible ritual
sparagmos,
while the
god reverts to his function of
divine
spectator
at the drama he himself
has
arranged
on
stage.
I
have chosen
to
begin
with the
robing
of
Pentheus,
for
beyond its
dramatic
impact
within
the
context of the
play, the mechanics
of
this scene
also
suggests
in its
details a wider and more
emblematic
set
of
significations. These
refer both
to
the
conditions of
Dionysiac
ritual itself as a
deadly
version
of
initiation into
the
mysteries
of
the
god's
worship
and
to the
conditions
of the
theater
of
Dionysus
and the
accepted
terms of its artistic
representations.2
For the
first,
Pentheus
must be dressed as a woman
for
consecration
to the
god
as the
surrogate
beast-
victim he will become
in
the ritual
on the
mountain;
for the
second,
the
costuming
of Pentheus reminds us that the theater
requires
mimetic
disguise by
which it
creates
and
maintains
its
status as dramatic
festival.3 Thus
through
this
scene we
arrive at the
dynamic
basis
of
Greek
drama,
catching
a
momentary
glimpse
of
the
secrets
of
its
ritual
prehistory
as
it
merges
with and is
imitated
by
the
tech-
niques
of the theater.
In
particular,
the fact that Pentheus dons a feminine
cos-
tume and rehearses
in it
before
our
eyes exposes
perhaps
one of the
most marked
features
of
Greek
theatrical
mimesis, namely
that men are the
only
actors
in
this
civic
theater;
in order to
represent
women
on
stage,
men must
always put
on
a
feminine costume and mask.4 What this means
is that it is not
a woman who
speaks
or
acts
for herself and in herself on
stage;
it is
always
a man who
imper-
sonates her.5
Still
further,
if
we
also consider that
in
order
to
direct
the
proceedings
of
the
drama,
to
manipulate
its theatrical
effects,
contrive
its
plots,
set its
stage,
and
control its
mimetic
play
of
illusion and
reality,
Dionysus,
the
god
of the
theater,
must
also take on
womanish
traits,
then
perhaps
we
may
venture
yet
further: can
there
be some
intrinsic connections
linking
the
phenomenon
of Athenian
trag-
64
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
edy, invented
and developed
in a historical context
as
a
civic art form,
and
what
the society culturally
defines
as feminine
in
its
sex/gender system?6
There is
nothing new
in
stressing
the associations of
Dionysus
and the fem-
inine for the
Greek theater.
After all, madness,
the irrational,
and the emotional
aspects
of
life are
associated
in the culture more
with
women than
with men.
The boundaries
of women's
bodies are perceived
as more fluid,
more permeable,
more
open
to affect
and
entry
from
the
outside,
less
easily
controlled
by
intel-
lectual and
rational means.
This perceived physical
and
cultural instability
ren-
ders them weaker
than men;
it is also all
the more a source
of
disturbing power
over them, as
reflected
in
the
fact
that
in
the divine world it is
feminine agents,
for the most part, who,
in
addition
to
Dionysus,
inflict men with madness-
whether Hera, Aphrodite,
the
Erinyes,
or even Athena as in Sophocles' Ajax.
On
the other
hand,
we might want to
view
the androgyny
of
Dionysus,
already
in
Aeschylus
called a gunnis
(womanish man)
and pseudanor
(counterfeit
man,
frag.
61
Nauck,
2nd ed.), as
a true mixture
of masculine and
feminine. This
mixture,
it
can
be argued, is
one of the
emblems of his paradoxical
role as dis-
rupter
of
the
normal social categories;
in
his
own person he
attests
to the coin-
cidentia
oppositorum
that
challenges
the hierarchies
and rules
of the
public
mas-
culine
world,
reintroducing
into it confusions,
conflicts,
tensions, and ambiguities,
insisting always
on the more
complex nature
of
life than masculine aspirations
would allow.7 Such a view would stress
male and
female
aspects
alike;
it would
regard the god
as embodying
a
dynamic process
or
as
configuring
in
his
person
an
alternate
mode
of
reality.
Convincing
as this view
may be,
it
runs the
risk
of
underrating
the
fact
that
it
is
precisely Dionysus'
identification with the
feminine
that gives
him
and
his theater their
power.
Along
the same lines,
in
the
quest
for
equivalence
between
the
genders,
one
could remark,
not without
justice,
that
although
all
the
actors are
male
in
tragedy,
we
find
that
within the
plays
feminized
males are countered
by
masculinized
women: for
example,
Aeschylus' Clytemnestra
of the
"man-counseling
mind"
(Agamemnon),
Euripides'
Medea, and,
of
course,
the
maenadic
Agave herself,
who
in
the Bacchae
boasts of her warrior
prowess
over the
body
of
Pentheus,
as
yet unrecognized
as
the son whom she has killed.
This notion
of
a balanced,
symmetrical
inversion
finds
support
in
Greek
festivals outside
Athens where
men
and women
change
their
costumes
for a
day,
each imitating
the
appearance
and
behavior
of
the other.8 Better
yet, there is evidence
that
in initiation rites at
puberty
or
sometimes
in
nuptial
arrangements,
young men and
women
in
their
own
spheres
temporarily adopt
the dress and
behavior
of
the
other sex.9 Such
reversals are
usually explained
according to
a ritual logic that
insists that each
gender
must for
the
last
time,
as
it were,
act the
part
of
the other before
assuming
the
unequivocal
masculine and feminine identities
that cultural ideology
requires.
10
As
a
theoretical concept, this
proposition
makes eminent sense.
On the level
of
practice,
however, these symmetries
are often
more apparent
than real; the
Playing
the Other
65
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
notion conforms
better
with our
habits
of binary thinking
than
with recorded
evidence
as these
rites are far better
and
more numerously
attested
for men
than
for women,
not least
because their
performance,
aimed
at creating
men
for the
city, is of
greater concern
to the
culture at
large.
Second, and more
to
the point,
critics
treat inversion
of roles
as a sufficient
explanation
in
itself,
that is, a
temporary
reversal before
its decisive
correction.
They do
not extend
their analysis
to consider
what
the various
aspects
of the
actual experience
might imply
for achieving
male identity.
What
more specifically
might these
actions
and attitudes
teach him?
How might
the processes
of
imitat-
ing the feminine
prepare
him
for access to
adult status,
other than
to teach
him
the behaviors
he must
later scrupulously
avoid? Unless
there
were something
to
learn and
something
necessary
to repeat,
we would not
need the
genre of tragedy
at all to call these different
roles into question
and,
most of all,
to challenge
the
masculine civic and
rational
view of the
universe.
Finally,
the pairing
of
feminized
men and masculinized
women, a
useful
notion
in
many respects,
runs the risk
of
assuming
mutually
inverted categories
without looking
to the
internal
dynamics
of
tragic
conventions that shape and
predict the
conditions
of
this
exchange.
Even more,
such a
concept tends
to
reduce
the scope
of
the feminine
in
the
drama. It
is too limited
to encompass
her double
dimensions-a
model
of both weakness
and strength,
endowed
with
traits and
capacities
that have
negative
and
positive
implications
for
self
and
society.
Thus
my emphasis
falls
not
upon
the
equal
interchange
or reversal
of
male
and
female
roles
but
upon
the
predominance
of the feminine in
the
theater,
a
phenomenon
that
used
to
(and
may still)
puzzle
some
commentators,
who
per-
ceived
a serious discrepancy
between
the mutedness
of women
in
Athenian
social
and
political
life and
their
expressive
claims to be
heard and seen
on
stage.'
And
my
focus
on
imbalances rather
than
on
equivalences
between
the
genders
is aimed
here
not so
much at the
content
and
themes of the various
dramas
in
their
political
and
social dimensions
but on the
implications
of theater and
the-
atricality
as
these
are
integrally
related to and
reflective
of the thematic
preoc-
cupations
of drama.
If
tragedy
can be viewed
as
a
species
of recurrent
masculine
initiations,
for
adults
as well as
for
the
young,'2
and
if
drama,
more
broadly,
is
designed
as
an education
for its
male
citizens
in
the
democratic
city,
then
the
aspects
of
the
play
world
I
wish to
bring
into
sharper
relief
may
well merit
the
speculations
I
am about
to
offer on
theater, representation,
plot
and
action,
experience
and
identity-all
linked
in some radical
way
with the feminine.
From the
outset,
it
is
essential
to understand
that
in
Greek
theater,
as
in
fact
in
Shakespearean
theater,
the self
that is
really
at stake
is to be identified
with
the male, while
the
woman
is
assigned
the
role
of the radical
other.'3 It seems
unfair
perhaps
that,
given
the
numbers
and
importance
of female
protagonists
in
Greek
tragedy (by
contrast,
it should
be
said,
to
the case of
Shakespeare),'4
66
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
theoretical
critics
from Aristotle
on never
consider
anyone
but the male
hero
as
the central
feature
of the genre;
they
devote
their attention
to
outlining
his
traits,
configurations,
and
dilemmas.
Yet
despite Clytemnestra,
Antigone,
Phaedra,
Medea,
and many
others, it
must be acknowledged
that
this critical
blindness
is
also insight.
Even
when female
characters
struggle
with the conflicts
generated
by the
particularities
of their
subordinate
social position,
their demands
for
iden-
tity
and self-esteem
are
nevertheless
designed primarily
for
exploring
the
male
project
of selfhood
in
the larger
world
as these
impinge
upon
men's claims
to
knowledge,
power,
freedom,
and self-sufficiency-not
for some greater
entitle-
ment
or privilege,
as
some have thought,
that the
female
might gain
for
herself,
not even
for revising
notions
of what
femininity
might be
or
mean.
Women as
individuals
or chorus
may give
their names
as titles
to plays;
female
characters
may
occupy the center
stage
and leave
a far
more indelible emotional impression
on their spectators
than
their male counterparts
(as
Antigone,
for
example,
over
Creon).
But functionally
women
are never
an end
in
themselves,
and
nothing
changes
for them
once they
have lived
out their drama
on
stage.
Rather, they
play the
roles
of
catalysts,
agents,
instruments,
blockers, spoilers,
destroyers,
and
sometimes
helpers
or saviors
for the male
characters.
When
elaborately repre-
sented,
they may
serve as anti-models
as well as hidden
models
for that masculine
self, as
we will
see,
and,
concomitantly,
their
experience
of
suffering
or
their
acts
that lead
them
to disaster
regularly
occur
before and
precipitate
those
of
men.
15
An excellent
case
in
point
is
Sophocles'
Trachiniae,
a
play
that will serve us
well
throughout
this
essay.
Although
the distress and
despair
of
Deianeira,
the
innocent,
virtuous
wife, commands
our
attention
for most
of the play,
and
although
she
loses none
of our
sympathy
when
unwittingly
destroying
her hus-
band Heracles
for love of
him, we come
to realize that
her entire
experience,
her
actions
and
reactions, are
in
truth a
route for achieving
another
goal,
the real
telos or
end of the
drama. She
is the agent
designated
to
fulfill the deceptive,
riddling
oracles which
predict
the tragic
destiny of
Heracles
rather than
a well-
earned respite
from his labors here on
earth.
She kills herself
offstage
in remorse,
but his are the sufferings
we
witness publicly
on
stage, and
it is he who,
in his
first and
last appearance
before
us, provides
the
climax and
resolution
of the
drama.
Moreover,
if
we consider
more
generally
that the
tragic
universe
is one that
the
specifically
male
self
(actor
and/or
spectator)
must discover
for
himself as
other
than
he
originally
imagined
it to
be,
then the example
of
Deianeira is
particularly
instructive
for
articulating
the
complex
position
occupied
by
that
feminine
other.
For in the course of
the
action,
Deianeira indeed does
come
to
that
discovery
for herself,
realizing
too late that she
had been duped.
The love
charm the centaur had bequeathed
to her
was
in fact a
deadly
poison,
whose
fiery potential
had
been concealed within
the recesses
of
the
house until
exposed
to the
warming
heat
of
the sun. But
her
education
into the treacherous
opacity
Playing
the Other 67
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
of the tragic world
holds no interest for Heracles,
preoccupied as he is
with
unraveling the riddle
of his own story. The ensemble
of her life and death seems
to have nothing to
teach Heracles that he can
acknowledge openly on his death-
bed, and, even
more telling, neither will he allow
it to have meaning for their
son Hyllus when
he prescribes for the boy's future
in terms that define him only
as his father's son.
Medea
in
Euripides'
play comes closest to the
demand for an equivalence
of
that
feminine
self to the male, preferring, as she
says, to stand three times in
the
van
of
battle than
to
bear
one
child (Medea
250-51).
Yet
although she has
a
defined
geographical
destination
to
which
she will
go once she leaves Corinth
in
exile, having obtained
in advance from its
king the promise of sanctuary
in
Athens,
her
spectacular
departure from the
city on the dragon chariot of
her
immortal ancestor,
the Sun, suggests that there
can
be
no place
for
her
in the
social structure down
here
on
earth.
A woman who insists on the
binding
nature
of the
compact she
made
on her own
with
a man, who defends her right to honor
and
self-esteem
in
terms suspiciously
resembling those of the male heroic code,
and finally
who
would
reverse
the cultural flow
in
founding a new genre of poetry
that celebrates now the exploits
of women rather than those of men
(as
the chorus
sings, 410-45)
is meant not
for
human but superhuman status.16 Accordingly,
it
is only logical that
she disappear
once
the drama
is over-upward and out
of
sight. Yet even in
this revolutionary play the typology
still holds. Medea's formal
function
in
the
plot
is to
punish
Jason
for
breaking
his sacred
oath
to
her,
through
an
exacting
retribution of
tragic justice,
and
she is the
typical
and
appropriate
agent,
even
if embodied
in
exotic
form,
for
accomplishing
that crucial end.
Let us return
now to the central
topic-to
identify
those
features that are
most
particular
to
drama, serving
to differentiate
it
from all
other
art
forms that
precede it: narrative
(epic),
choral
lyric
and
dance,
solo
songs,
and
perhaps
even
stylized exchanges
of
dialogue. Though profoundly
indebted,
to be
sure,
to
ritual
representations
and
reenactments,
to ritual costumes and
masks,
drama
develops
along
the
deeper
lines
of
character
and
plot
and establishes
its own
conventions
and entitlements
in the more secular
sphere.'7
At the risk of drastic
(I repeat, drastic)
oversimplification,
I
propose
four
principal
elements as
indispensable
traits
of the theatrical
experience,
all inter-
linked
in
various ways
with one another and
to the sum total of the
tragic
spec-
tacle. And
I
will assume another
more
dangerous
risk
by boldly proposing
in
advance that
each of these
traits can find
not its
only,
to be
sure,
but
its
more
radical cultural
referent
in
the traits and
aspects
that the
society
most associates
with the feminine domain.
First,
the
representation
of the
body
itself
on
stage
as such-its
somatic
dimensions and
the
sense
of its
physical
reality. Second,
the
arrangement
of
architectural
space
on
stage
that
continually suggests
a
relational tension between
inside and
outside.
Third,
the
plot itself,
that
is,
the
strategies by
which theater
68
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
best represents
a
tragic story
on stage
and contrives
to bring
that story
through
often
surprising
means to
the
conclusion
that the terms of its myth
demand.
In
this sense,
plot
as shape
of the
story
often coincides
in
fact,
as we will
see,
with
the other
connotation
of plot
as intrigue
and deception.
And finally,
the most
extensive
category-the
condition
of theatrical
mimetism
itself,
limited
in this
discussion
to the
question of
role playing
and disguise-or
more generally,
the
representation
of
a self as other
than
it seems or
knows itself
to be, a
self with
inner and
outer dimensions.
The
Body
The
emphasis
in
theater
must
inevitably
fall
upon
the
body-the
per-
forming body of the
actor as
it embodies
its
role,
figures
its
actions,
and is
shown
to us
in
stylized poses,
gestures,
and
attitudes.
We see
this
body
before us in
the
theatron,
the viewing
place,
in rest and
in movement.
We observe
how it
occupies
different areas
at
different
times
on
stage,
how it
makes its entrances and
exits,
how it
is situated
at times
alone or,
more often,
in
relation
with
others. This
performing
body
engages
at
every
moment
its
sensory
faculties-to
hear, see,
touch,
and move;
above all,
it
is the
actor as
body
or
body
as actor
who
projects
the human voice
in
all its
inflections.
Theater
has been
defined as "the
adventure of
the human
body,"'
8 but
for
Greek
tragedy
it would
be more accurate
to
call
it "the
misadventure
of
the
human
body."
What
interests the audience
most in the somatics of the
stage
is
the body
in
an
unnatural state
of
pathos
(suffering)-when
it
falls
farthest
from
its ideal
of strength
and integrity.
We notice
it most
when it is
reduced to
a helpless
or
passive
condition-seated,
bound,
or constrained
in
some other
way;
when
it
is in the
grip of
madness or
disease,
undergoing
intermittent
and spasmodic
pain,
alternating
between
spells
of
dangerous
calm before the stormy
symptoms
assail the
body again.
Tragedy
insists
most
often on exhibiting
this
body,
even
typically
bringing
back
corpses
killed
offstage
so as to expose
them
to public
view.
When characters
are still
alive,
some
demand us to witness the
spectacle
of their
suffering
so we
may pity
them. Others
call
for
a covering to
hide
their shame
or
wish to be hidden
inside
the house-or
in
some supernatural
way to vanish
from
the
eyes
of the
beholders.
More to the
point, it is
at those
moments
when the
male finds himself
in a
condition
of weakness that
he too becomes
acutely
aware
that
he
has
a body-and
then
perceives
himself, at
the limits
of pain, to
be most
like
a
woman.
Heracles,
at the
end of
Sophocles'
Trachiniae,
when his flesh is being
devoured
by
the poison of the
fateful
robe, appeals
to his son:
"Pity me,
/ for I seem
pitiful
to
many others,
crying
/
and
sobbing
like a girl, and
no one
could ever
say / that
he
had
seen this man
act like that
before.
/
Always
without
a
groan
I
followed a
Playing
the Other
69
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
painful
course. / Now
in
my misery
I am
discovered
a
woman" (Trachiniae
1070-75;
cf.
Euripides
Heracles
1353-56). Sophocles' Ajax,
in
despair
after the
madness
that
the
goddess Athena had sent upon him has abated and determined now to
die
a
manly
death that will
restore
his heroic
image to himself, considers the
temptation to yield through pity to his
wife's
entreaties.
If
he tempers his will,
his
tongue that is hard and firm like a sword, he has blunted its sharp edge; he
has
in effect feminized
it,
as he
says (ethdlunthen,
for the
sake of a woman [Ajax
650-52]).
A
warrior man
often likens himself to
a
sword;
his
mind is obdurate,
his
will and words
are
whetted
like iron
(cf. Aeschylus Seven Against Thebes 529
-
30,
715). His is
the instrument of
power
that
wounds others, while his body remains
impenetrable to outside forces. Ajax
will
harden his will; he will have his heroic
death
by
the
sword
of
iron.
But how?
By burying
that
sword
in
the earth
and
falling upon it, breaking through
the
flesh
of
his side
(pleuran diarrexanta, 834).
As he
violates
the
boundaries
of his
body,
he
also violates tragic convention by
staging
his
death
as a
public
act.
Yet
paradoxically,
there is
yet
another
anomaly
in
the method
he
chooses. Suicide
is
a
solution in
tragedy normally reserved only
for women-and what we
are
given
to witness is
this convention borrowed for a
man's version
of it. A heroic death then
in the
woman's
way,
a
whetted
will
pen-
etrated
by
a whetted
weapon, befitting (as
we
will discuss
further
in
another
context)
the curious
ambiguities
of
this
most
masculine hero.'9
My
last
example
here is
Hippolytus
in
Euripides' play. Refusing eros, refusing
the
touch,
even the
sight
of a
woman,
he is
brought
back on
stage
in
mortal agony
after his horses had
stampeded
in
fright
before
the
apparition
of the bull from
the
sea. Then
he
cries
out that
pains
dart
through
his head
and
spasms leap up
in his
brain,
while
his desire
is
now all for a sword to cleave himself in
two
and
"put
his life at
last to bed"
(Hippolytus 1351-52, 1371-77).
His
symptoms
are those
of
a
woman,
racked
with
the
pain
of childbirth
or
the torment of
sexual desire.20
We remember
then
Phaedra's
last
words,
which
prophesied
that
he
would
"share
in her
disease" (Hippolytus 730-31)-the deadly pangs
of
unrequited
eros that
earlier had reduced
her
to a sick and
suffering body.
Yet in
that
first
scene,
when
no one
on
stage yet
knows the cause
of her
malady,
the chorus
speaks
in
generic
terms about the
body
of a woman.
They
call
it
a
dustropos harmonia,
an
ill-tuned
harmony;
it suffers
the
misery
of
helplessness (amechania),
and is
open
to the
breeze
that darts
through
the
womb
in
pregnancy
as well as to the
torments
of
eros.21 This
body
is
permanently
at
odds
with
itself, subject
to a
congenital
dis-
sonance between
inside and outside. Woman
can never
forget
her
body,
as she
experiences
its
inward
pain,
nor
is
she
permitted
to
ignore
the fact of its
outward
appearance
in
that
finely
tuned consciousness
she
acquires
with
respect
to
how
she
might
seem to
the
eyes
of
others.
Bodiliness is what most
defines
her in
the
cultural
system
that associates
her with
-physical processes
of birth
and death
and
stresses the
material dimensions
of
her
existence,
as
exemplified,
above
all,
in
Hesiod's canonical
myth
of how
the first
woman, Pandora,
was
created.22
Men
70
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
have bodies, to be sure,
but in the gender system
the role of representing
the
corporeal side of life in
its helplessness and submission
to constraints is primarily
assigned to
women.
Thus, it
is
women
who most
often tend the bodies of others, washing
the
surface
of
the body
or
laying
it out for its funeral. Theirs is the task to supply the
clothing
that covers
the
body,
and
they
have a storehouse
of robes that
may
encircle the male
victim
in
its textured folds.
When men
suffer or die
in
the
theatrical space,
it
is
the
female
who most
typically
is the cause. She seems
to
know, whether
consciously
or
not,
how
vulnerable,
how
open-how
mortal,
in
fact-is the
human
body.
These
figures may
be goddesses like Aphrodite
and
Hera or,
above
all,
the
Erinyes, avenging
ministers
of retributive
justice.
But these
are also women
like
Clytemnestra, Deianeira,
Hecuba, and, of course, Agave,
the
mother of Pentheus.23
On
the other
hand,
dressed as a
woman,
Pentheus makes the first discovery
of
his corporeal
self. Before this
he
defends
himself
militantly against any
touch
of
the other.
But now
he
allows Dionysus
to make
contact with his
body
and,
in
a
grotesque parody
of female
coquetry,
is
eager
for the
god
to
adjust
the fine
details
of his costume and
to
arrange
the
stray
locks of hair
peeping
out
from
beneath its snood (Bacchae
925-38).
With this
laying
on of
hands,
Dionysus
breaches that physical
integrity
so
dear
to the male
and
prepares
Pentheus
for
the terrible
sequel,
when the
voyeur, coming
to see
as
a
spectator
what he
imag-
ines are the women's
illicit
physical
contacts with others,
is
himself
exposed
to
view,
his
body
becoming
instead the focus
of their
ministering
hands.
Then
they
indeed
touch
his
body,
and
in the
strength
induced
by
their maenadic state easily
tear it
apart
in
the literal act
of
sparagmos.
In
this primitive
regression, women
undo the body; its structures cannot
hold, its limbs are
unbound, and the masculine
self, originally so intent
on
oppos-
ing himself to anything
feminine, is fragmented
and flies apart. Female violence
may
be viewed
through
the lens
of role
reversal,
but in the
Greek imagination
the
maenadic
woman is
regularly
endowed with
this
power, especially
over
the
masculine
body,
and
is the
model
herself
for
the male
who,
when he too is seized
like
Euripides'
Heracles
in
the grip
of
this madness,
can only be described
as
"playing
the Bacchant" and imitating the part
of the woman.24
Theatrical
Space
Second
is the
space
itself
on
stage
in
the
Greek
theater,
where the
human actors situate themselves and the theatrical
action takes place before
the
spectator. By
convention this
space
is
constructed
as an outside in front
of a
facade of
a
building,
most often a house
or palace,
and there is a door that leads
to
an
inside that
is
hidden
from
view. What happens
inside must always in some
way
be
brought outside-for
example, through
use of the wheeled platform
Playing the
Other 71
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
called the ekkyklema, most
often used to display the corpses of those
bodies who
have met their fatal doom
within the house-visual proof of
the violence that
must also by convention take
place offstage. But the very business
of entrances
and
exits,
of
comings
and goings through the door of the
house, continually
establishes a symbolic dialectic
between public and private, seen and
unseen, open
and
secret, even
known and unknown.25
In this simple mapping
of spatial relations, the stage conventions
not only
chart
the
bounded areas
of social relations between the genders,
which assign
men to the outside and
women to the inside, but they also suggest
an analogy to
the
tragic world itself, which
in the course of its plot and actions
inevitably reveals
its hidden and unknown
dimensions.26
Earlier I defined the tragic universe as one that is other than
the self origi-
nally imagined it to
be.
Going
one step further, we may add that
tragedy is the
epistemological form par
excellence. What it does best through
the resources of
the
theater is
to
chart a path
from ignorance to knowledge, deception
to reve-
lation, misunderstanding to
recognition. The characters act out
and live through
the
consequences of
having clung
to a
partial single
view of the world and them-
selves.27 In the
process,
in
the conflicts and tensions that
mark
the
relations
between the opposing characters,
all come
in
some way to experience
the com-
plexities
of
the world-its
multiple dimensions, its deceptions
and illusions. Inside
and outside
organize
the
dramatic action
of the
drama,
and
they
refer
not
only
to the shifting planes of
reality (the known
and
the
unknown)
but to the
tragic
self-both
mind
and
body-and
find their
material
referent
in
the house
and
the
facade
it
presents
to
the
outside world.
The
house,
let
us now
observe,
is the
property
of
the
male
and his
family
line. The oikos
is
the
visual
symbol
of
paternal heredity
that
entitles sons to
succeed their
fathers as
proprietor
of
its wealth
and movable
goods
and
as ruler
over its inhabitants.
As the male
in
tragedy
is often
conflated with
king,
the house
extends further as
a locus
of
masculine
power
to include
the
sign
of
sovereignty
over the
city
as
a
whole,
and the
solidity
of
its architectural
structure
symbolically
guarantees
the
enduring
stability
of the social order.
Yet the
house,
as
we
know,
is more
primarily
the
proper
domain
of the
woman,
to which
the
social
rules of
the
culture
assign her,
while
its
men
go
forth
into the outside world to
pursue
manly accomplishments
in
war
and
politics.
Thus,
in
conflicts between house and city
or
between domestic
and political
concerns that are
the recurrent
preoccupations
of
tragic plots,
the
woman, whether
wife
or
daughter,
is shown
as best
representing
the
positive
values and
structures
of
the
house,
and
she
typically
defends
its interests
in
response
to some masculine
violation
of its
integrity.
As a
result, however,
of
the stand
she
takes,
the woman
also
represents
a subversive threat
to male
authority
as an
adversary
in a
power
struggle
for control that
resonates
throughout
the
entire
social and
political
72
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
system,
raising
the terrifying specter
of rule
by
women.
Here
we
might
note
how
strongly alien
is the presence
of this
feminine
other
who,
in
asserting
legitimate
values most
associated
with
her
social role,
is also
perceived
as
illegitimately
asserting
the rights
reserved
for the masculine project
of
self.
She never achieves
these
in
any
permanent
way.
But in the contest
over rights to
control
domestic
space
that
the stage
conventions exploit,
it is
the
woman and
not the man who,
by
reason
of her close
identification
with the
house as
her intimate
scene,
consistently
rules
the relations
between
inside
and
outside
and shows
herself
as
standing
on
the
threshold
betwixt
and between.
Men find
out
in tragedy
that
they are likely
to
enter that
interior
domain
mostly to
their
peril,
whether
Agamemnon
as
he
walks upon
the
crimson
carpets
his
wife has
spread
to lead
him to his death
at
her hands
within the
house,
or
Hippolytus
confronted
inside
with the
nurse's revelation
to
him
of Phaedra's
guilty
secret that
is the
beginning
of his
doom,
or
Polymestor
in
Euripides'
Hecuba
whom the Trojan queen
lures
into the tent to
take a woman's
revenge
on
the
perfidious
Thracian
king
who
has killed
her child.
As a
general
principle,
the
absent hero returns
to his house
either
never
to
enter through
its
doors
again,
as for the extreme
case of Heracles in the
Trachin-
iae,
or to meet
with
his own destruction
within,
as
in the cases cited
above,
or
finally,
like the Heracles
in
Euripides'
play,
to
go
mad
once inside the
house,
slaying
his wife
and
children and
literally
insuring
the fall
of the house
by
top-
pling
its columns.
On the other
hand,
if
the
male would successfully
penetrate
the
interior
of the house
and reclaim
it for
his
own,
he typically
requires
feminine
assistance,
best exemplified
in the fact
that,
as we
will
discuss
further
in
a different
context,
all
the extant
versions
of
Orestes' story
insist
upon
pairing
him with
his
sister,
Electra.
Men
imagine
they
can control that interior
space
by attempting
to control
the women within
it,
and
they object,
often
violently
as Pentheus does
in
the
Bacchae,
when
in
the
most dramatic
reversal
they leave
the stifling
environment
of
the
house
to venture
forth to the
open
(although
equally
uncivic
world)
of
forest and
mountains.
But the
king's
authority lapses
on all fronts.
He
is unable
to
bring
back
his Theban women
from the mountains to
put
them
in
their rightful
place,
-ultimately-going
out
to
meet
them
on
their new
terrain
with the
results
we
already
know. But he
fails too
on
domestic
territory
when
he
would
lock
up
the
other maenads
(and
their
leader
Dionysus) and
imprison
them
within
the house.
Literally
binding
them with
fetters,
he discovers
all
too
soon the
futility
of
apply-
ing
coercive
force as
they easily-magically-loosen
themselves
from his
restraints,
while his
larger
demands
for
mastery
over
the
house literally
collapse
when
Dionysus sends
the
earthquake
to
shake the
oikos to
its very
foundations.
The situation
of
Pentheus leads
to
a
further
point.
The
king erects
barriers
around himself
(and
his
psyche)
against
the invasion
of
Dionysus
even as
he
Playing
the Other
73
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
struggles to maintain the
integrity of the house and the walled city of Thebes.28
If tragedy,
as I have suggested, is the epistemological genre par excellence,
which
continually calls
into
question
what we know and how we think we know it, it
does so
often by confronting
the assumptions
of
rational thought with those
psychological necessities that
may not be denied.
The master example of
Pentheus therefore gives another turn to the dialectic
of
inside and outside that
focuses on the woman and the house as containers for
the
emotional energies
of
the self
and
the
society. The
house has its
many kinds
of
secrets that men do not
know, and the challenge
to
male authority over it
therefore takes place on several
levels-the social, cognitive, and psychological.
If
men enter this domain,
assuming their legitimate rights to its custody, only to
meet with a welcome they had not
foreseen,
at the same time
they
also
inevitably
fail to
lock
up,
to
repress
those
powerful
forces hidden
in
the recesses
of
the
house. Quite the
contrary-tragic process,
for
the
most
part, conveyed through
the catalyzing person and
actions
of
the
feminine, puts
insistent
pressure
on
the
facade of
the masculine self
in
order to bring outside that which resides unac-
knowledged and unrecognized
within. Here in the Bacchae, where the inversion
of
roles is expressly posed
in
spatial terms that send the women outside and
situate the man within, the
stage conventions are used to their best
effect as
Pentheus leaves the interior
space now for the last time-for his liberation and
for
his destruction-dressed, as we
might
now
expect,
like
a woman.
The Plot
Third,
the
plot
itself-that which
brings
about the
recognition,
the
anagnorisis-the plot
whose
process
Aristotle
describes
as
a
combination
of
desis,
binding, and lusis, unbinding,
denouement,
and which
in
its
complex
form
he
calls
by the corresponding Greek
term,
a
sumploke,
an
interweaving
as that which
describes
the
fabric,
the texture
of
the
play (Poetics 1455b).
At a
higher level, these
terms are even more
suggestive
as
they might
remind
us how the
tragic
world
works
its
ruinous effects
through
modes
of
entrapment
and
entanglement
that
causes
its characters first to stumble
through ignorance
and
error and then
to
fall.
In
the elaborate
tragic game,
the
metaphoric patterns
of
binding
and
unbinding
continually operate
in
a
reciprocal
tension as
signs
of
constraint and
necessity,
on
the
one
hand,
and
of
dissolution
and
death,
on
the
other, defining the parameters between
which characters
are
caught
in
the
"double
bind."29
In
the cognitive psychology
of
tragic man,
inner
choice and external
necessity
(or ethos, character,
and
daimon,
divine
power) finally converge
to sanction what-
ever form of
tragic justice
the
plot
demands
for
its
satisfying
fulfillment. Thus
the
"nature
of
tragic
action
appears
to be
defined
by
the
simultaneous
presence
74
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
of a 'self'
and something
greater at
work that is divine."30
In this
sense, the gods
finally may
be said to
direct the energy
of the
action and to
be understood
retrospectively
as supporting
and advancing
the outcome
of the
myth.
Gods sometimes
appear
on
stage
(and
I have
already
remarked how fre-
quently these
figures are
goddesses),
although most
often they
operate
from afar
as inhabiting
that other
unknown dimension
of existence
which mortals
may only
grasp dimly
and, of course,
too late.
But it is remarkable
how often
that energy
is channeled
through
the feminine
other, who serves
as their
instrument
even
when
she
acts or seems
to act on her
own terrain
and
for her
own reasons
and
even
when
she acts out
of ignorance
or of only partial
knowledge
of the
tragic
world she
inhabits.
Thus women frequently
control
the plot
and the activity
of
plotting and
manipulate
the duplicities
and illusions
of the tragic
world.
On the one
hand,
women's exclusion
from the
central area of masculine
public
life seems
to be matched by
their
special
access
to those
powers beyond
men's control,
to
those outside
forces that make
sudden
forays
into
human
lives,
unsettling
all
their
typical
assumptions.
On the
other
hand,
that same
exclusion
which relegates them
to the inside as mistresses
of the
interior
space
equips
them
for deviousness
and
duplicity, gives
them a
talent,
or at least
a
reputation,
for
weaving
wiles and fabricating plots,
marks
of their double
consciousness
with
regard to
the world of
men.
Tragedy
is the
art
form,
above all,
that makes the
most of
what
is called
discrepant
awareness-what
one character knows
and the other
doesn't
or
what
none of the
characters
know but that
the audience
does. Thus
it is that irony
is
tragedy's
characteristic
trope, that several
levels of
meaning operate
at the same
time. Characters
speak
without knowing
what they
say, and
misreading
is the
typical and
predictable
response to the
various cues
that others
give.
This
pervasive
irony may manifest
itself in many
ways, and
it
owes
its effec-
tiveness
to
a strong conviction
about the
ambiguous,
even opaque
nature of verbal
communication
that is
reflected
in the belief in oracles.
These
riddling,
divine
utterances invite
interpretation
and/or evasion
and,
at the same time, suggest,
when the outcome
proves
disastrous,
how
misguided
and
ignorant
these
human
attempts
may
be.
Apollo
and his oracle often serve as a
primary
source,
as Oed-
ipus,
his most
famous
client,
confirms. But other factors
make for
dramatic
irony,
particularly
in connection
with
the
deceptive powers
of the feminine
and
the
special
verbal skills that
accompany
these.
Clytemnestra
in
Aeschylus' Agamemnon
is the
most powerful
paradigm of the
woman
who plots, who
through the riddling
doubleness
of the language
to which
she
resorts
builds the play
to its climax
in the murder
of her husband
within the
house where
she entangles
him in the
nets of the
robe, and
only Cassandra,
another woman of second sight, perceives
but cannot
convey
what lies behind
the guileful
persuasion.
The case of
Phaedra, the
virtuous wife
in Euripides'
Hippolytus,
is also instructive.
Caught
in the conflict
between desire
and honor
Playing
the Other
75
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
and
determined
to
preserve
her integrity
at
any cost,
Theseus'
queen,
despite
herself
or rather
in
defense
of that
apparently
indefensible
feminine
self, fab-
ricates
the lying
message
that
will implicate
Hippolytus
as the
cause of
her death
and lead to
his literal entanglement
in the reins
of
his own chariot.
The pattern
holds
too even
at the
other end
of the
dramatic
spectrum
where
in the late romantic
plays of
Euripides,
which
shift to
exotic locales,
the
feminine
other takes
on a
different configuration
as
the remote
object
of a mythic
quest.
Now men are
sent
forth, albeit
unknowing,
in search
of the
absent,
forgotten
woman
who longs
to return
to the
home and
loved
ones she
has
lost; in
the
process
of rescuing
the
feminine,
they
find out
they have
redeemed
and
refound
a version of male
heroic
identity.
But
still
it is the
woman
who plots
and now
openly
devises a plan
on
stage
before
us-this time for
the best
of reasons-her
own rescue
and that
of
her menfolk,
as does Iphigenia
in the Iphigenia
in Tauris
or Helen in the play
of the same name.
The men here
are only
adjuncts
of
the
women;
they offer prior
schemes of
their
own but inevitably
yield to
and coop-
erate
in
the woman's
superior
plans
that all involve elaborate
dramas
of
deception.
If we take a rapid
inventory
of
the plot as
intrigue
in the
extant
plays of
the
tragic
corpus,
some interesting
principles
emerge.3'
First,
it is
the women
whose
plots
are more
generally
successful.32
If men
succeed,
however,
it is
precisely
because they
have
allied themselves
with women-for
example,
in the Euripidean
plays
just cited,
and
more
broadly
in the various treatments
of the Orestes
story
where
Orestes
succeeds
in
avenging
his father
through
the murder of
his
mother
because he
has
joined
forces
with his
sister,
Electra.
Thus the
recognition
between
them must
necessarily
precede
the
praxis
of
vengeance.
In the
Choephoroi
of
Aes-
chylus
(the
second
play
of the
Oresteia),
for
example,
it
is
only
after the
long
interchange
between himself,
Electra,
and the female
chorus of libation
bearers
that
Orestes
is
able
at last
to
interpret
the dream
of
Clytemnestra,
and
thus,
psychologically
equipped,
is
ready
to
assume a
stranger's
disguise
that will
gain
him
successful
entry
into
the
feminine
domain
of
the
house.33
Second,
whereas
deceit and
intrigue
are condemned
in
woman,
they
are
also
seen as natural
to her
sphere
of
operations
and the
dictates of her nature.34
For
the
male,
however,
resort
to
dolos,
trickery,
is
what
most undermines masculine
integrity
and
puts
him under
the
gravest
of
suspicions.
These are best
mitigated
when the
one
to be deceived
is a
cruel,
barbarian
king
of
another
land
(as
in the
late
Euripidean
plays)
whose
adversary
status
comes closer to
the role of melo-
dramatic
villain.35
The case of Orestes
at home in
Argos
is
even
more
infor-
mative
in
this
regard.
His
success,
it is
true,
depends
on
reunion
with his
sister,
but his
resort
to
trickery
and
disguise
(dolos,
mechane)
entails
a further risk to
his
masculine
stature,
no
matter
how
urgent
and
obligatory
is his task
of
vengeance.
Appeal
to
the
authority
of
Apollo
the
god
is therefore
needed to
justify
this mode
of
action.
The
god (in
both
Aeschylus
and
Sophocles)
must
explicitly
decree
a
76
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
retribution
that
exactly
matches
the
original
crime:
as
she
(Clytemnestra)
killed,
so
must
she
be
killed in
turn-by
guile
(Aeschylus
Choephoroi
556-59;
Sophocles
Electra
32-37).
Sophocles'
Trachiniae,
that
schematic
model of
gender
relations,
again
sup-
plies
an
excellent
version
of
the
norm.
Heracles
too
practices
deception, first
to
conquer
the
girl
Iole, the
current
object
of his
erotic desire
and the
immediate
cause of
all
his
woe,
and then
to
introduce
her
secretly
into
the
house. But in
his
case,
deception
returns
quite
literally
(and most
dramatically)
against
him.
His
deception,
revealed
by others to his
wife, activates
the
Centaur's
ruse,
plotted
long
ago
as
the
deadly
poison
entrusted as
a
secret
love
charm to
Deianeira's
safekeeping
inside
the
house. The
point is
that
innocent
as
Deianeira
may
be of
conscious
intent
to harm
her
husband,
she still
easily
proves a better
and
more
successful
plotter
than he.
Masculine
guile
is
repaid
in
full-even when
retalia-
tion
does
not
openly
bear
the
name of
revenge.
If this
Heracles
conforms
so well
to the
normative
pattern,
Ajax,
that other
great
hero,
does
not.
His
is a
curious
case,
but
one
whose
anomaly
might
just
prove
the
point. At
the
crucial
moment
of
Sophocles'
play,
having determined
to
die
an
honorable
death, he
delivers a
deceptive
speech that
suggests
he has
changed his
mind and
has
learned
to bend with
the
vicissitudes of time
and
change. With
this
speech
he
puts
off
those
who
would
guard
him
and
leaves
himself
alone
to
stage
that
elaborate
suicide
to
which
I
have
earlier
referred.
Critics
have
energetically contested the
status of this
speech
as truth or
lie. For
while
the
outcome of the
plot
tells us
that
Ajax
has
not
undergone
any funda-
mental
conversion
of
spirit,
he also
seems to
have
arrived
at the kind
of
tragic
knowledge
we
recognize
as
intrinsically
true to
the
genre.
How
then
can we
read the
enigma
of
this
speech?
Better
still,
how
can
we
read
Ajax,
the
traditional
epic
hero,
who
would resort
to a
deceptive
plot
that
goes
against the
grain of
strict
masculine
values
in
which
Ajax
puts
too
much
store? This is the
man,
after
all,
we
might
note with
respect
to
spatial
relations,
who
could not
endure,
as the
oracle
riddlingly
suggests
for his
salvation,
to
remain
inside
the tent
even for the
space of
one
single
day. But it
is
precisely
the
ambi-
guities
of this
hero who
in his
madness
has
not
acted
the
part
of
the
hero
and
precisely
the
question
of
dishonor
converted
finally
to honor
that
account
for
the
interesting
ambiguities
of
his
subsequent
actions,
which
rewrite
the
theatrical
conventions
associated with
gender.
Thus
the
deceptive
speech
makes
sense as
a
feminine
strategy
enlisted
in
the
service of
restoring
an
unequivocal
manliness
that
he
can
only
achieve,
as
I
suggested
before,
by
dying
the
manly
death-
heroically
and
publicly
on
stage-yet
in
the
woman's
way.
Now when
other
male
characters,
those not
designated
as
tragic
figures
in
the
dramatic
action, seek to
deceive,
their
devices
flounder,
and men as
these
are
dismissed
out of
hand.36
Agamemnon,
so
easily
duped
by
his
wife in
Aeschylus'
Playing the
Other
77
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
play,
miserably
fails,
for his
part,
when in
Euripides'
Iphigenia
in Aulis
he
and
Menelaus
plot
to bring
Iphigenia
as
a sacrifice
for
the expedition
to Troy
under
the
pretext
of a marriage
with Achilles.
Clytemnestra
finds
them
out-by
a for-
tuitous
accident-and
the sacrifice
only takes
place
through
Iphigenia's
voluntary
and open
choice of
the role
assigned
to her
by
her father
and
the myth.
Most
telling
of all
perhaps,
Odysseus,
the master
plotter
on his own
epic
territory
(and
a familiar
trickster figure
in
the
plots
of
mischievous
satyr
plays),
only sees
his
plans
go awry
on the tragic
stage-for
example,
in Sophocles'
Philoctetes
when
Neoptolemus,
son
of
Achilles, rejects
finally
the
man and
his plans,
he of
whom
his
father
had said
in the Iliad,
"I
hate like
the gates
of Hades
a
man who
hides
one
thing in
his heart
and
speaks
another"
(9.312-13).
The Bacchae
finally,
as
we might
expect,
furnishes
the
most remarkable
exam-
ple
of
the uses
of
plotting
and exposes
the conventions
of
its theatrical
deploy-
ment
as
the pivotal
point
around which
the entire play
revolves
and
the peripeteia
depends.
All the
operative
terms come into
play-secrecy,
guilefulness,
entrap-
ment,
and femininity-as
Dionysus
and Pentheus
engage
in their
power struggle
for control over
the
other,
the
city,
the
women,
and ultimately, over
the
outcome
of
the plot
itself.
Pentheus aligns
himself,
of course,
with physical
force
as the
masculine means
to victory, trying
and failing
to bind his adversary
(and
his
followers),
and ready
to dress as
a
soldier
and
deploy
an
army
for
a
military
battle
against
the
women.
What
Dionysus
does is to
retaliate
against
threats
of
force at
this critical
moment with
a devious
plot-to
entice
Pentheus
to
go
alone
to
the mountains
in
secrecy.
What
this
means
is that he
persuades
Pentheus
to trade his
ready
reliance
on
physical
combat
for
that
other,
diametrically opposite
mode
of action-resort
to a
cunning plot
of
self-concealment.
In other
words,
Dionysus'
strategy
for
victory
over
his
opponent
is first
to lure him into
embracing
the same kind
of
strategy.
They
are
co-conspirators
now, plotting
together
but for
ultimately
diver-
gent
results,
as
for one
the
intrigue
will
succeed
in
every respect
and
for the
other
it will
disastrously
fail.
But the
first conquest
of Pentheus
already
lies
in the
fact that he
agrees
to
shift
his tactics
from
open
force to the
secret
deception
of
hiding,
and the
second,
which
follows
upon
the
first,
is the
change
in
dress
from male
to female
that,
as
Dionysus
argues,
is essential
for
the
success
of the
project.
These
two
steps,
however,
imply
one
another-it
is the
woman who
has recourse
to
devious
plot-
ting,
the
very charges
Pentheus
has laid
against
both
Dionysus
and the maenads
(e.g.,
475,
487,
805-6),
and
the costume Pentheus
dons
therefore
matches and
visually represents
the feminine
nature
of
the
strategy
he
has
already
chosen.
But
in
the
ways
of women
Pentheus
is
only
an
imposter,
easily
betrayed
by
the
other
superior
plotter,
and hence
the scheme
he contrives
and carries
out
can
only
recoil
against
him for
his own
doom.
78
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Mimesis
I come now
very briefly
to
my
fourth and most inclusive
element-
that of
mimesis itself,
the art of
imitation through
which
characters
are ren-
dered lifelike
and plot
and action offer
an
adequate
representation
of
reality.
Yet
mimesis
also focuses
attention
on
the status of
theater as
illusion, disguise,
double dealing,
and pretense.
There
is
a
serious
and wonderful
paradox
here.
For while
theater resorts
continually
to artifice,
as
it
must,
to
techniques
of
make-believe
that can
only resemble
the real,
it
can
also better represent
the
larger world
outside
as it more nearly
is, subject
to
the
deceptions,
the
gaps
in
knowledge,
the tangled
necessities,
and all the
tensions and
conflicts of
a
complex
existence.
Role
playing
is
what actors
must
literally
do
in the theater
as
they
don their
costumes
and masks
to
impersonate
an
other-whether
king
or
servant,
mortal
or
god,
Greek or
barbarian,
man or woman. But the reverse side of the coin
is
to be
dubbed an actor,
a
hypokrites,
who
is
only
playing
a
role, offering
only
a
persona (a
prosopon)
to
the other
that does not match what lies behind the
mask.
Recognition, anagnorisis
of persons
whose
identities were
unknown
or
mis-
taken is,
of course, a typical
and even
focal device of tragic
action.
But this kind
of
recognition
is the
overtly
theatrical
event
that
condenses
the
epistemological
bias
of
the entire phenomenon
of drama.
Thus
recognition
extends
along
a far
wider spectrum,
embracing
the world,
the other, and
the self.
The
problem
of
accurately
reading
the other is a
continuing,
obsessive concern
in
Greek
tragedy
that increases
in urgency
as the genre
displays a
greater self-consciousness
with
regard
to its own theatrical
resources.
But recognition
of
the
unknown self,
as
for
Oedipus,
or of the hidden
self,
as for Pentheus
or
even for
Deianeira,
is
perhaps
the
most elusive
but also
the most
psychologically
significant result
on
the
tragic
stage, suggesting
what the
invention of
theater for and
in the city
might
imply
about an
emerging
image
of the private
individual
and the growing
pains
of masculine
identity.37
This double dimension of role playing is a feature
that Greek society would
perceive
as not
exclusively
but
yet
fundamentally
feminine.38 Woman is
the
mimetic
creature par excellence,
ever since
Hesiod's Zeus
created her as
an imitation
with
the aid of
the other artisan
gods and
adorned
her with a deceptive
allure.39
Woman is
perennially
under
suspicion
as the one
who
acts a
part-that
of
the
virtuous wife-but
hides
other thoughts
and
feelings, dangerous
to
men,
within
herself
and the house.
"Counterfeit
evil"
is the
charge
that
Hippolytus
is
not
alone
in
bringing against
the
genos,
the race of
women,
for she
has the best
capacity,
by her nature
and origin,
to say one thing
and
hide another
in
her
heart,
to sow
the doubt
in her husband's
mind, to cite
perhaps the
radical cause,
that
the child she
bears
may be his but again
may
not be.40
Playing
the
Other 79
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Woman speaks on the tragic
stage, transgressing the social rules if she
speaks
on her own behalf. In this role,
her speech and action involve her in the
ensemble
of tragic experience and thereby
earn her the right to tragic suffering.
But by
virtue of the conflicts generated
by her social position and ambiguously
defined
between inside and outside,
interior self and exterior identity, the
woman is
already more of a "character"
than the man, who is far more limited as
an actor
to his public social and political
roles. Woman comes equipped with a
"natural"
awareness
of
those very complexities
men would resist, if they could. Situated
in
her more restrictive and sedentary
position in the world, she is permitted,
she is
asked, we might say, to reflect
more deeply, like Phaedra, on the paradoxes
of
herself. Through these she can
arrive better at the paradoxes of the
world that
she,
much
better
than
men,
seems to know is subject to irreconcilable
conflict,
subject as well to time, flux,
and change (the very themes I might add
of Ajax's
great deceptive speech). Hence
the final paradox may be that theater
uses the
feminine for the purposes of
imagining a fuller model for the masculine
self,
and
"playing the other" opens
that self to those often banned emotions
of fear
and
pity.
Woman
may
be
thought
to
speak double,
and
sometimes she does.
But she
also sees double; the culture
has taught her that too, and it is perhaps
not an
accident that
only
when Pentheus dresses as
a woman
does he see
double for the
first
time-two suns,
two Thebes. This
is
a symptom
of
madness,
to be
sure,
attributed
by
the
ancient
commentators
to
inebriation,
but
madness
is the emblem
of the
feminine,
and
seeing
double
is also the emblem
of a double
consciousness
that a man
acquires by
dressing
like a woman
and
entering
into the
theatrical
illusion. The very
fact of that
dressing up already
demonstrates
the
premise
in
unequivocal
and
theatrical
terms.
The feminine
is a
tragic
figure
on the
stage;
she is also
the mistress
of
mimesis,
the heart and soul
of the theater.
The feminine
instructs
the other
through
her
own
example-that is,
in
her
own name
and under
her own
experience-but
also
through
her
ability
to
teach
the other
to
impersonate
her-whether
Pentheus
or
Dionysus.
This
brief discussion
can
suggest only
in
outline
how
closely
the
tragic genre
in
its theatrical
form, representation,
and content is
linked to Greek notions
of
gender,
and how
for the most
part
man is
undone
(or
at times
redeemed) by
feminine forces or
himself
undergoes
some
species
of
"feminine"
experience.
On the
simplest level,
this
experience
involves a shift
at the crucial
moment of
the
peripeteia
from active to
passive,
from
mastery
over the self
and others
to
surrender. Sometimes
there is
madness, always suffering
and
pathos,
which
lead
in
turn to
expressions
of lamentation
and
pity
from the chorus
and/or the char-
acters. In a
more
complex
view, tragedy,
understood
as the
worship
of
Dionysus,
80
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
expands an awareness
of
the
world and
the self
through
the drama
of
"playing
the other" whose mythic
and cultic
affinities
with
the
god logically
connects
the
god
of
women
to
the lord of the
theater.
If drama, however,
tests masculine values
only
to find that these alone
are
inadequate to the complexity of the new
situation,
it
also,
as
Linda Bamber
remarks, "does not dismiss them"
but
rather most
often shows
that manliness
and self-assertion
need
no longer
compete
with
pity
and even
forgiveness.4'
Moreover,
the male characters whose sufferings
are
the most
stringent
and reduc-
tive of self are also allowed to discover
the internal strength
for
transcending
them.42 In the end, tragedy arrives at closures
that generally
reassert
male,
often
paternal, structures
of
authority,
but before
that the work of
the drama is to
open up the masculine
view
of
the universe.
It
typically
does
so,
as
we have
seen,
through energizing the theatrical
resources of the female and concomitantly
enervating
the
male
as the
price
of initiating
actor and
spectator
into new and
unsettling
modes of
feeling, seeing,
and
knowing.
We
can trace the
persistence
of
this
"initiatory" process
from the work of
the
first tragic poet to the third.43 History
has cunningly arranged
it that
Euripides'
last play, the Bacchae, should
also
refer
back
to
the
archaic scenario
that underlies
the ritual conditions of the theater.44 Yet
viewed
in its
metatheatrical aspects,
the
Bacchae also makes claims to be considered
in a diachronic
perspective
as a belated
examplar
of the
genre
that
by
now has
developed
a
keen awareness of
its own
properties and conventions. As a result,
the play is in a position to exemplify
and
reflect back what was always implicit in the
theater, and at the same time, by the
very admission of that theatrical awareness,
to transform
its
object
of
reflection
and reorient
it
in
new and different directions.
If
my basic hypothesis
is
valid, then
the
distinctive features of Euripidean
theater (which are more obvious, in fact,
in plays other than the Bacchae) may
well lend support to
what
I have been suggesting
about the intimate relations
between the
feminine
and the
theater.
Thus
I
see all the
following traits of Eurip-
idean drama as various and interlocking
functions of one another, starting with
Euripides' greater interest
in and skill at subtly portraying the psychology of
female
characters,
and
continuing
to his
general emphasis
on interior
states of
mind
as well
as on the
private emotional
life of the individual, most often located
in
the feminine
situation. We may add to
these his particular fondness for plots
of
complex intrigue (usually suggested
by women) that use dolos, apatp,
technp,
and
mechane,
which
with
their resort to
disguise
and role
playing
are an
explicit
sign
of
an
enhanced
theatricality. Finally,
we may include
more
generally Eurip-
ides' thematic concern
with
metaphysical
questions of reality and illusion in
the world.
The Helen is the
most
splendid
example,
as it
is
a
drama
that
allows itself the
fullest play
with the
resources
of theater and
uses these
to direct the
most elab-
Playing
the Other 81
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
orate
inquiry
into
the complexities
of being
and
seeming
and
the
paradoxical
crossings
of
illusion
and
reality.45
The source
of the
confusion
is the
ontological
status
of the feminine
itself.
There are
two
Helens,
the
real,
chaste
version
who
was left
in
Egypt
and
never
went
to Troy,
and
the
more traditional
adulterous
wife whom
Menelaus
thinks
he has
recovered
at
Troy
but is
really
a phantom,
an eidolon,
impersonating
Helen's
true self.
I alluded
earlier
to
the symbolic
impli-
cations
we
might
infer from
Pentheus
dressing
as
a woman
and
seeing
double
for the first
time.
Here
in the
Helen, where
double
vision rules
the
play
in
every
respect,
the
woman
is
both a
character
who
to her
irremediable
sorrow
learns
first
hand
about
the
most
fundamental
problems
of
the
self's
identity
and,
at
the
same
time,
serves
as an objective
referent
through
which
the
man
must
question
all his previous
perceptions
of the world.
What
is
more,
the essential
strategy
for
insuring
the success
of
the
intrigue
she
invents
for
their
rescue
requires
that
he
too
adopt
a disguise
and
pretend
to be
another
than
himself,
allowing
her
to
recount
the
most
dangerous
fiction
that the
real
Menelaus
has
died.
The
uses
of
the play,
to be
sure,
have
their deadly
serious
side
for
all con-
cerned,
and the unhappy
residue
of
spoiled
lives persists
behind
the successful
outcome
of the
play.
But for love of
this
woman,
whether
in
her
imagined
or
real
persona,
the man
willingly
enters
into the
theatrical game
and shows
a capacity
now
to act a
part
and
enter
into a
stage
illusion. The
Helen is
a rare play
that
pushes
its
original
improbable
(and
theatrical)
premises
as far
as
they
can
go,
but
the uxorious
Menelaus
is also a
novelty,
and the
erotic
element already
diverts
the
play
away
from the
more typical
tragic
mode
to that of
romance.
In
this new
kind of
play
world
Euripides
invents,
the uses
to which he
puts
the feminine
and
the theater
may
be
seen as
the
logical
result
of the
premises
of
tragedy.
On
the
other
hand,
by
disclosing
those
premises
too
well,
he also
alters them
and
sub-
verts
the
genre
that
was so
firmly
bound
up
with
the
context
of the
masculine
civic world.
Thus,
in
this sense,
Euripides
may
be said
to have
"feminized"
tragedy
and,
like his
Dionysus
in the Bacchae,
to
have laid
himself
open
to the scorn
that
accrues
to those
men
who
consort
with women.
Aristophanic
comedy,
which loves to
lampoon
Euripides
and all his
newfangled
ideas,
continually
presses
the scandal
of his erotic dramas,
especially
those
that let
women
speak
more
boldly (and
hence more
shamefully)
upon
the
stage
until
Aristophanes,
in
his
own late
play,
the
Frogs,
evaluates
on
a full-fledged
scale
the development
of the
tragic
genre
by
staging
an
open
contest
between
the old
poet,
Aeschylus,
and the
new,
Eurip-
ides
(755-1853).
At
stake
is
the choice
of
which
poet
Dionysus
should
bring
back
from the
underworld
to the
city
and theater
of
Athens. Which
one
is more
worthy
to save
the
city,
which seems
to
link its loss
of
political
potency
to the
absence
of a
fertile,
potent
poet
in
the
tragic
theater?
Broadly
stated,
the contest
develops
into
one
between
masculine
and
feminine
sides,
with
Aeschylus
espousing
a
manly,
virile
82
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
art that
exhorts its
citizens
to
military
valor
and
Euripides representing
a
femi-
nine, slender Muse
who
is weaker and more
insubstantial, leaning
toward
the
sensual and
the
pathetic.
Not
surprisingly,
when
these two are tested
in
the
scales,
Aeschylean tragedy outweighs
the
Euripidean by
its
superior
mass and
weight.
Dionysus therefore abandons his original desire for Euripides,
to whose seductive
allure he
had
earlier
succumbed,
in favor of
resurrecting
the
heroic
warrior
energies of
the earlier
poet and, by extension,
of the
past.46 Aristophanes
not
untypically assumes
that when
things go badly
for men and masculine
interests
the cause lies in a decay of moral and aesthetic
values that slides
easily
into hints
of
effeminacy
and all
that that
implies.
In
any case,
the solution
of
the
Frogs
in
bringing
back
the
archaic
spirit
of
Aeschylus as a solution to the city's problems is also
a
formal, generic
one.
It
is
predicated on the controlling convention of Old Comedy that fulfills its festive
function of social renewal by consistently choosing
the
idealized past
over the
distressing,
chaotic
present,
even as
it
prefers
to
rejuvenate
the old
(father)
rather
than, as in New Comedy, to promote
the
young (son). Moreover,
the comic
poet
paints
with a
broad,
satirical
brush,
and whatever the
justice
or
truth of the cause
he thinks he
is
advancing (and
his
play,
of
course,
is
what
he
imagines
will save
the city), he
has
the generic right
to
misrepresent,
and
how he
does
it
here affects
Aeschylus even
more
perhaps
than
Euripides.
Leaving
aside
the fact that
Euripides
too has his
military
and
patriotic plays,
Aristophanes
would have us believe
that
the essence
of
the Seven
Against Thebes,
that drama
"full
of
Ares"
invoked to
support Aeschylus' case,
was some conven-
tional
treatment
of
military prowess.
It
was
rather
a
tragedy concerning
the
sons
of
Oedipus
and
the
dangers they posed
to the
safety
of
the
city by
their
resort
to
armed combat
in the
style
of the old heroic
duel,
while
the
function of
the avenging Erinys returning to
fulfill
the father's curse conforms precisely,
even schematically, to the rules of the feminine
in
the theater as I have earlier out-
lined them.
Nevertheless, Aristophanes
is a witness we
cannot afford to
ignore.
He
speaks
about the
theater from
within
the theater. Skewed as his caricature of Euripides
(and
his
drama) may be,
his
strategy
of
clustering the poet's theatrical, psycho-
logical, and noetic innovations around a particular affinity for the feminine is
valuable
testimony to
a
popular contemporary perception of Euripidean theater,
even
if it
is
bought
at the
price
of
suppressing the continuities
with
earlier drama.
Along the
same
lines, we may even be able to swallow Aristophanes' parting
shot that
implies Euripides' loss of the tragic art is due to "sitting at the feet of
Socrates"
(1491-95),
another favorite
target for comic misrepresentation. Yet
however justified Aristophanic comedy may be to single out both Euripides and
Socrates
as
spokesmen
for the new intellectual
trends that
confuse
and
unsettle
the
older, simpler (hence more manly) values of the city, philosophy would never
consort
with
tragedy, which
it
comes to see as its implacable rival in laying claim
Playing
the Other
83
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
to teach
the truth, impart
knowledge, improve
its fellow citizens,
and without
doubt-to
save the city.
Socrates,
as Plato
in the
next generation
has
him
argue, makes
no distinction
whatsoever
among any of
the tragic poets
when he comes to discuss
the theatrical
arts. Indeed, he founds
his
critique
of drama on Homer, whom
he characterizes
as the first teacher
and
guide
of
tragedy.47
That
same Aeschylean
play is invoked
again
when Socrates'
interlocutor in the
Republic
first
quotes
a famous verse from
it
in a
proper
context only
at
the next moment
to
turn
around the meaning of
the lines
that follow
it
so
as to apply
it
to the
unjust
man
rather
than to the
just.48
The argument
in Plato between
tragedy
and philosophy is well
known, and it is
not
my intention to
air all the old questions
or
to solve
the old dilemmas. But I
want
to suggest
that Plato, standing outside
the
drama,
can be called
in as
a last
witness
to support my
claims about
the intrinsic
links
between femininity
and
theater,
viewed now
from a wholly negative
perspective.
Plato's insistence
on
banishing tragedy
from
his
ideal state
and his consistent distaste
throughout
his
career
for
the
tragic poets,
whom
he sometimes associates
quite closely
with
sophists
and rhetoricians,
are
based,
to be
sure,
on a number of
complex
and
disparate
factors.
But in
addition
to the
explicitly
philosophical
issues,
I want to
argue
that
Plato's
position
on theater can also
be illuminated
by considering
its
relation to his
notions
of
gender
and his
attitudes toward
the
feminine.49
Strange
as
it
may
seem,
Plato's
aim
is not
all that
remote
from what
Aris-
tophanes
wants
in the
Frogs.
The
project
is more far-reaching,
to be sure, in
every
respect,
and the
means are those which will
forever
change
the
shape
of
Western
thought. But,
like
Aristophanes,
Plato is
concerned
with
restoring
men
and their morals
in the
city, and,
like
the comic
poet,
he insists
on
the
relevance
of
aesthetic style
and
form.
Briefly put,
for the
purposes
of
this
discussion,
Plato's
larger
concerns
may
also
be translated
into his
general
desire to remake man in
a masculine
society
and
through philosophical
training
to
purify
and
enhance
the traditional
heroic notion
of manliness
(andreza)
in
a
new,
revised version
in
which
courage, vigilance,
and
strength may
be
better
utilized
for the
improve-
ment of self and
society.
Certainly,
Plato
comes closest
to
codifying
under the name of
philosophy
the
dream of the Greek
male
for a world that is constituted
as
his
alone,
where he
might
give
birth to himself and aspire
finally
to
an
immortality he
has
always
craved.
In
tragedy,
this desire leads
to
disaster,
most
often,
as we have
seen,
through
the resistance
of the
gods-and
of
the
women. Philosophy,
on the
other
hand,
offers the
promise
of success
in this
endeavor, providing
one follows the
blueprints
that are
carefully designed
to retrain the masculine self.
It
may
be
objected
that Plato breaks
with
the
old
stereotypes
of
gender
when
he
insists
that women
may
be
just
like
men with the
exception
of a natural
infe-
riority
in
physical strength,
which
does
not
disqualify
them from
participating
as
guardians
(and
even
warriors)
in his vision of the ideal
city
in
the
Republic.
84
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
This is
a revolutionary
proposal
whose
significance
we ought
not
minimize.50
But we
should
note
that
this reevaluation
of
women
does
not really upgrade
the
feminine
in its
differences
from
the
masculine.
Quite
the
contrary-Plato
defuses
the power
and
specificity
of the
feminine
when he
would
abolish
the family
and
the domestic
sphere
in which
that
influence
operated.
If he
includes
the
partic-
ipation
of certain
women
who
may
prove
to possess
masculine
abilities,
it
is
precisely
because
in
the Republic
he believes
that
they
may be
successfully
taught
to
imitate
the
masculine
model.
Even
here,
the principle
of equality
falters
when
Plato
would reward
with special
breeding
privileges
men
who
have
distinguished
themselves
in
battle
but does
not
suggest
granting
the same
opportunities
to
their
female counterparts.
This may or
may
not be
a
trivial slip.
What is
striking,
however,
is that
elsewhere
femininity
plays
for Plato
throughout
his work
its usual
role
of
negative
foil
to the
masculine
as
it heads
the
long
list of
undesirable
models
for men that
descends
to
the servile,
the buffoonish,
the
bestial,
and the
non-
human
(Republic
3.395d-396b).
Plato's
attack
on
tragedy
and
its
traditional repertory
operates
on
several
fronts:
he
objects
to the
deceptiveness
of theatricality
as a
misleading
and
defi-
cient imitation
of reality,
deplores
the often
unworthy
quality
of what or who
is
being
imitated,
and insists
upon
the
damaging
effects
such imitations are
liable
to produce
on the
actors and
spectators
in the
theater.5'
For the
first
case,
I would
not
go
so
far as to claim
that Plato
explicitly
refers
the art
of making
illusions
to the
feminine
per
se,
even
if
women,
like
children,
are
most
susceptible
to its
charms
(e.g.,
Laws
658d,
817c)
and most
likely,
in
fact,
to
tell
those lying
stories
about the
gods
to their
young
(Republic
377c).
But
Plato's
interest
never
focuses
for
long
on women
as
such
but
rather
on the
inferior
type
of
man,
who deceptively
passes
off
appearances
for
truth
and who
appeals
to
the inferior
parts
of
the
self (and
the citizenry)
that
will yield
to
the emotions
and
pleasures
(not
lessons)
of
make-believe.
Thus, although
he
confirms
the
conventional
dictum
that
woman
is inclined
by
nature
to be
secretive
(lathraio-
teron)
and crafty (epiklopoteron)
because
of her
intrinsic
weakness
(to asthenes)-and
concomitantly,
her
natural
potential
for
virtue
is inferior
to a
man's
(Laws
781
a-b)-Plato
hardly
sees
her
(or her
representation)
as a powerful
acting
force
in
the world of
men.52
But
by
a whole series
of innuendos
and
juxtapositions, poets
(and
artists)
are
enrolled in the
ranks of male
trickster
figures
who fall
furthest from
the ideal
of
manliness and
seek
only
to
cajole,
seduce,
and pander
to
the tastes of
their audi-
ence.
Imitators
(artists
and
musicians)
and
poets
and
their
entourage
of
actors,
dancers,
and
producers
join
the multitude
of
callings
that
are
signs
of
the
luxury
that
corrupts
the
primitive
city,
and
these directly precede
those
"makers of
all
sorts of
goods,
especially
those
that have
to do with women's
adornment";
the
sequence
then continues
with those
servants
like
"beauty-shop
ladies,
barbers,
cooks,
and confectioners"
(Republic
373b-c).
Playing
the
Other
85
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Once assimilated
to
the
larger category
of sophists,
dramatic art,
reduced
finally to prose
rhetoric on a
par with oratory,
shares in
the same field
of ref-
erence that likens
their
false imitations of justice
to those
activities practiced
by
and for women:
cookery (especially
confectionery),
which
"puts on the
mask of
medicine and pretends
to know
what foods are
best for the
body"
(Gorgias
464c-d),
and beauty-culture,
"the counterfeit
to physical training
...
a mischievous,
swind-
dling, base, servile
trade,
which creates
an
illusion by the
use of artificial
adjuncts
and make-up and
depilatories
and costume"
(Gorgias 465b-c).
All these arts
traffic
in
deceptive appearances,
and their effect on others is
to pander
to appetites
and pleasurable
gratification.
The Gorgias
stresses a certain
sensual, effeminate
pleasure.
But the
Republic,
in
which Plato
specifically
addresses
the
emotional
power
of the tragic,
empha-
sizes the
experience
of
pain
and
suffering,
and
evaluates
its
effects
on those who
act
in
and attend
the tragic
spectacles.
Here the association
with
the
feminine is
clear and explicit,
reiterated
each time Plato
returns to the
topic: when
heroes
are shown
to weep
and lament their misfortunes, they are
not only endorsing
a
false theology
about the justice
of the gods
but are weakening
themselves
and
others
by
their indulgence
in
womanish
grief
(Republic
387e-388a,
605d-e).
Such
a man does not remain
steadfast to himself, exercising
self-control
and
rationally pondering
the events that have
happened
to him. Rather he
gives way
to
cowardice,
terror,
and a host of conflicting,
changeful
emotions that
ill
suit
the model
of
a
brave and
noble manliness
that
the
state (and
the soul)
requires.
Worst of
all,
he entices
the
spectators
into the
pleasures
of
vicariously
identifying
with his pitiable
state,
and ends
by setting
them
the
example they
unfortunately
will learn to imitate
for themselves.53
For Plato,
who so often
strives to efface
or remove
all
mixture,
confusion,
and
changeability,
his
theory
of drama is
simple
because,
stripped
down
to
essences,
his categories
are also
simple.
The
mobility
of
temporary
reversals
and dialectical
play
with
opposites
already
introduces
a
cognitive
complexity
that is
the
sign
itself
of
a
dangerous
indeterminacy;
it
undermines the
principle
of
like
to
like
that
regulates
his
thought
and
is
designed, by
its
literalness,
to reinforce
a
simple
stability.
At the
most inclusive
level
is
the dictum that
no
man
can
play
more than
one
part,
in life
or
in
the theater
(e.g., Republic
3.394e-395b).
The other
is
always
weaker
and inferior to the
self,
whose
idealization
requires
that,
once
perfectly
established,
it cannot
change
and still be itself.
As
such,
that
lack of strength
(attributable
to
the
lack of
mastery by
the rational
faculty
and
hence equatable
finally
to
a lack of
wisdom)
can
be most
easily
codified
according
to the conventional
terms
of
the
society
under the
name
of
the
feminine
other,
to include
the
cognate negative
traits
of
cowardice,
fearfulness,
and emotional
lability. Hence,
in Plato's
reductive view
of drama and
of
gender, playing
the
other
is
a
species
of
wrongful
imitation
that threatens to
infect
reality
and
degrade
the
aspiring,
virile self.
It is therefore
forbidden,
above
all,
"for
a
man, being
a
86
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
man-in training,
in fact to become
a good/brave man,"
to imitate a
woman
in
any way whatsoever:
"whether old
or young, whether
railing against
her husband,
or boasting of a
happiness which
she imagines can
rival the
gods,
or
overwhelmed
with grief and
misfortune; much
less a woman
in
love,
or
sick,
or
in labor"
(Republic 3.395d-e).
Men
are neither permitted
to
impersonate
a woman
nor to
show
themselves
in a male
persona
as
undergoing
the
experiences
of a
woman,
precisely the routes
I have proposed
as leading to masculine
initiation
into the
lessons (and benefits)
of the tragic
world.
Limited as
his discussion of theater
may be, Plato,
as
a
spectator
who fails
to
come
under the
spell of tragic
mimesis
(or
who
perhaps
once did
and
was
cured),
nonetheless darkly
confirms the
inextricable
relationship between
theater and
the feminine. Tragedy
cannot control the
ambiguities
of
role
playing,
as most
particularly
when the male actor is
called upon
to
represent
the
woman who is
not under control
either because she
is actively unruly
or because she
succumbs
to
the
pressures
of her
body.
More
generally, tragedy
by
its
very
nature
and
intention
can make
no
solid
provision
for
controlling
the
ambiguities
of a world
view
that
theater is expressly designed
to
represent.
Thus
Plato,
from his
point
of
view,
is
entitled
to
deny
to "the solemn
and marvelous
poiesis
of
tragedy"
the
very task we
might agree
it is well
equipped
to
accomplish,
namely
that
of
impart-
ing "beneficial
if
unpleasing
truths,"
and to claim instead that it
gives
its
uncritical
and
vulgar
audience
what it desires
to see and hear
(Gorgias
502b).
Plato goes still
further
into the matter
of
gender
and
drama in
the
playful
contest
he
stages
between
theater
and
philosophy
in the
Symposium,
where the
party to
celebrate the
recent victory of the tragic poet,
Agathon,
at
the
City
Dionysia ends
with the crowning
of Socrates instead of
Agathon.
In mounting
his own rival drama to explore the
subject
of
eros,
Plato excludes the presence
of the feminine at the
banquet
but subtly
and
significantly
uses the categories
of
effeminacy
and
femininity
to
enhance
the
philosophical
position
that
is
meant
to
include
and
supersede
the
appeal
of the theater.
The
Symposium
is one of Plato's
most
artful and
complex
dialogues and deserves,
of
course,
much
fuller
discussion.54
It
is established early on that love
of
women
is
an
inferior sort of eros (181a-d).
This
is not the crucial point. But we
may
note
in
our context the persuasive
if unfair value of using Agathon as the
rep-
resentative of
all tragic art. Agathon
speaks last, just before
Socrates, and in
his
flowery speech
on
eros,
which
parodies
perhaps
the
very
play
that
earned
him
the
tragic
victory (anthos
=
flower),
he
demonstrates
the soft and effeminate
nature for which he was
known and which
Aristophanes
wickedly lampoons
in
his
comedies (e.g.,
Thesmophoriazousae).55
Although Aristophanes
in the Sympo-
sium
is made at the end to fall
asleep
before Agathon, thus
establishing his rank
in
the hierarchy
that leads from comedy to tragedy and
then to philosophy,
the
comic
poet
is
represented
as
a
far
more
robust character
than the tragic
poet,
and his contribution
to
the theme of eros is more memorable
and more substan-
Playing
the Other 87
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
tial.56
The contrast, to
be sure, is even
more striking
between the lovelorn
Aga-
thon
and Socrates,
whose physical
endurance and
resistance to pederastic
temp-
tation
attest to the
remarkable
self-control of this
soldier/philosopher/lover/hero.
On the other
side, however,
philosophy appropriates
for its own use
the one
kind of feminine
authority that the
culture
acknowledges as legitimate
when
Socrates names the
prophetic
priestess, Diotima, as the
source of his
initiation
long ago into the
sacred mysteries of
Eros and as the
original author
of the
inspiring discourse on
eros he now is
about to deliver.
The feminine retains
here
her
more instinctive
alliance with the
erotic as well as her
mysterious
connection
with
that other world and
its secrets
whose power we
have come to
recognize
when manifested in
the theater. And
the woman, armed
with the prestige of
her
sacred
vocation, is called
upon
to
instruct
men as to how
they might
transcend
feminine influence
and, through
the
sublimations of
pederastic love,
even
give
birth
to themselves.
In
Plato's counter-drama the female as benevolent
priestess
has no
cause
of
her
own to protect
and
no conflictual
interests
to
distract
her.
She is then free to
lend whole-hearted
support to the
cause
of
men and to
transmit to them
a
wisdom
without
tragic pain
that
may become
entirely
theirs.
She
imparts
a
myth about
the
genealogy
of Eros
that
makes the erotic
principle
a
male child
and
explains
his nature
by
assigning potency
and
presence
to his
father,
Poros
(Ways
and
Means),
and a
famished
emptiness
to his
mother, Penia
(Poverty),
who
deceitfully
(and
characteristically)
tricks the one who is
endowed
to
consort with
the
one
who is not.
In
suborning
theater
as
well as
the
feminine,
Plato's
drama
puts
the former
to
sleep
in the
presence
of
the
wakeful
philosopher
and
transfers
feminine
orac-
ular
power
to
Socrates-the
midwife-who
also
incorporates
the
Dionysiac
into
his
satyr-like image
of
Silenus.
In
the
process
Plato obviates the
tragic
necessity
that
requires
the
feminine
presence upon
the
stage
and whose
complicated
and
essential functions
in the
theater
of
Dionysus
we have followed
throughout
the
course
of
this
essay.
Notes
An earlier, reduced version
of
this
paper
was
presented
at a
conference,
"After The
Second Sex,"
held at the
University
of
Pennsylvania, and at a symposium honoring
Professor Helen Bacon at Barnard College in New York, both in April 1984.
I
wish
to thank the commentators
on
these two occasions, Carolyn Heilbrun and Marylin
Arthur, respectively, as well as others who participated in the discussion. Thanks also
to
the
members
of
the Women's Studies
Colloquium
at Princeton
University,
who
offered
acute and thoughtful
comments at the
presentation
of this
paper,
in
partic-
88
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ular, Natalie Davis,
Suzanne Keller, and Elaine Showalter. Finally, I am grateful to
Jack Winkler,
Simon
Goldhill,
and
Jean-Pierre Vernant,
who read the
manuscript
and
from whose incisive and
valuable criticism
I
have greatly profited.
1. E.g., Bacchae 451-59;
Dionysus
is
called thelymorphos,
351
(cf. Pentheus' description
as gynaikomorphos [his costume
as imitating
a
woman's, gynaikomimoi; 981]).
2.
For the fullest account
of this
hypothesis,
see Richard
Seaford, "Dionysiac
Drama
and
Dionysiac
Mysteries,"
Classical Quarterly 31 (1981): 252-75.
3. For the metatheatrical
aspects of this scene
in
particular (and the play as a whole),
see Helene Foley, "The
Masque of
Dionysus,"
Transactions of
the
American Philological
Association 110 (1981):
107-33; and Charles Segal, DionysiacPoetics
and
Euripides'Bac-
chae (Princeton, 1982), 215-71.
4. See
further
E
I.
Zeitlin,
"Travesties
of
Gender and Genre
in
Aristophanes'
Thesmo-
phoriazousae,"
in
Reflections
of
Women in
Antiquity
ed. Helene
P.
Foley (New
York
and
London, 1981), 169-217
(a shorter
version
appears
in
CriticalInquiry
8
[1981]: 301-28,
and
is
collected
in
Writing
and
Difference,
ed.
E.
Abel
[Chicago, 1982], 131-58).
5. It should be noted that,
unlike other public Dionysiac festivals
in
Attica (and else-
where)
where
both
men and women
participate,
the
City Dionysia
seems
to
belong
to
men only (with
the sole
exception
of a
girl assigned
to
carry
the
ritual basket
in
the
preliminary
procession).
6.
The question
I
raise here
about
the
development
of
drama
in
Athens
and
its
political
and social motivations
is
obviously
too
complex
for this limited discussion.
I
would
suggest merely that the
historical conditions
of
drama, interestingly enough,
coincide
with
a period
that
sharply polarizes
definitions
and
distinctions of masculine
and
feminine roles.
Drama,
like the
woman,
we
might say,
is
useful
for its
society,
and
at
the
same
time
potentially
subversive and destructive.
It is
also
worth
remarking
that
as
theater reaches
its
full
flowering
in
the fifth
century,
the
iconography
of
Dionysus
undergoes a shift
in
the vase
paintings from a masculine, bearded figure to one,
more
youthful, who displays
effeminate and
more
androgynous features.
7.
For the bisexual
consciousness of Dionysus, see especially James Hillman, The Myth
of Analysis (Evanston, Ill.,
1972), 258-66.
For
the more
general paradoxes
of Dio-
nysus' role, see the
synthesis of Segal, Dionysiac Poetics, 10-19.
8.
These festivals are occasions for riotous
carnival (e.g., the Cretan Ekdysia, the Argive
Hybristika). Dionysiac
merriment also lends itself to such behavior, at least as Philos-
tratus, a
late
source,
describes
a painting
of
a Dionysiac revel: "Dionysus is accom-
panied by
a
numerous train
in
which
girls mingle
with
men,
for
the revel (komos)
allows women to act the
part
of
men,
and
men
to
put
on
women's
clothing
and
play
the woman"
(Imagines
1.2).
9. On
the various forms of transvestism
in
Greek
rite and myth, see Marie Delcourt,
Hermaphrodite: Myths
and
Rites
of
the Bisexual
Figure
in Classical
Antiquity, trans. J.
Nichol-
son
(London, 1956),
1-16; Clara Gallini,
"II
travestismo rituale di Penteo," Studi e
materiali
per
la
storia
delle
religioni
34
(1968): 211-18, esp. 215,
n.
6;
and Walter
Burkert,
Structure
and
History
in
Greek
Mythology
and
Ritual
(Berkeley, 1979),
29-30.
10. "For both sexes the initiation
through
which a
young
man
or
woman
is
confirmed
in
his
or her
specific
nature
may entail, through
a
ritual
exchange
of
clothing, temporary
participation
in
the nature of the
opposite
sex
whose
complement
he or she
will
become
by being separated
from it"
(Jean-Pierre Vernant, "City-State Warfare,"
in
Myth
and
Society
in Ancient
Greece,
trans.
J. Lloyd [Sussex, 1980], 24). Cf. also Henri
Jeanmaire,
Couroi
et
Couretes
(Lille, 1939),
153,
321.
See
further Pierre Vidal-Naquet,
"The Black Hunter and the
Origin
of
the Athenian Ephebeia" and "Recipes for Greek
Playing
the
Other
89
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Adolescence,"
in R.
L. Gordon,
ed., Myth, Religion,
and Society
(Cambridge,
1981),
147-85.
I
borrow
his term, "law
of symmetrical
inversion."
11. The
best recent discussion
of the
question is
Helene
P.
Foley,
"The Conception
of
Women
in
Athenian Drama,"
in
Reflections of
Women in
Antiquity,
127-68,
who offers
a
judicious
and nuanced
analysis
that, however,
leans too far
perhaps in
seeking a
matched
symmetry
and reciprocity
between masculine
and feminine
roles.
12.
On
tragedy as initiation,
related both
to
the
mysteries
and
to
puberty rites,
see
the
discussion
of Seaford,
"Dionysiac
Drama" (drawing
upon the
early pioneering
work
of
George
Thomson, Aeschylus
and
Athens, 2nd
ed. [London,
1946]). For
aspects of
puberty
ritual
reflected
imaginatively
in
the various
dramas
see, for Aeschylus'
Ores-
teia,
Pierre Vidal-Naquet,
"Hunting
and Sacrifice
in Aeschylus' Oresteia,"
in Jean-
Pierre
Vernant and
Pierre Vidal-Naquet,
Tragedy
and Myth
in Ancient Greece,
trans. J.
Lloyd
(Sussex,
1981), 150, and F
I.
Zeitlin,
"The Dynamics
of Misogyny:
Myth and
Mythmaking
in
the
Oresteia," Arethusa
11
(1978):
149- 84 (now
in Women and
the Ancient
World: The
Arethusa
Papers,
ed.
John
Peradotto and J.
P.
Sullivan
[Albany,
1984]); for
Sophocles'
Philoctetes,
Pierre
Vidal-Naquet,
"Sophocles'
Philoctetes and the
Ephebeia,"
in
Tragedy
and Myth,
175-99; for
Euripides'
Hippolytus, see
especially Charles
Segal,
"Pentheus
and Hippolytus
on
the
Couch and
on the Grid: Psychoanalytic
and Struc-
turalist
Readings
of Greek
Tragedy,"
Classical
World
72 (1978-79):
129-48,
and
F
I.
Zeitlin, "The
Power of
Aphrodite:
Eros
and
the Boundaries
of
the Self
in
Euripides'
Hippolytus,"
in Directions in
Euripidean
Criticism, ed.
Peter
Burian (Durham, N.C.,
1985),
52-111,
187-206;
and for the
Bacchae,
in addition to Seaford, see Segal,
Dionysiac
Poetics,
chap.
6,
"Arms
and
the Man: Sex
Roles and Rites
of
Passage,"
158-214.
Also
relevant
to these speculations
is Louis Montrose,
"The
Purpose
of Playing:
Reflections
on a
Shakespearean
Anthropology,"
Helios [n.s.]
7.2 (1980):
51-74, who discusses
the
public
functions
of
Shakespearean
theater as a
secularized
means
of
confronting
the
transitions
of
life that had
earlier been
framed
in
the
milieu of Catholic ritual.
13.
I
am
indebted here
to
the
stimulating
discussion
of Linda
Bamber,
Comic
Women, Tragic
Men:
A
Study of
Gender
and
Genre
in
Shakespeare
(Stanford,
1982),
as much
for
its
provocative
arguments
as
for
its
use
in
confronting
some fundamental
differences
between
the
feminine
in
Greek
and Elizabethan
tragedy.
There are
other
"others,"
to
be
sure,
on
the
Athenian
stage (e.g.,
barbarians, servants,
enemy antagonists,
and
even
gods),
but
the dialectic
of
self
and other
is
consistently
and
insistently
predicated
on
the
distinctions between
masculine and
feminine,
far
more even than
in
Shake-
speare.
Even the
plays
with
more
strictly
military
and
political
themes
(excepting
only
Sophocles'
Philoctetes) arrange
their
plots
around
critical confrontations
between
mas-
culine
and feminine.
14.
No Shakespearean
tragedy has a
woman as
its
main
character, although
sometimes
she
shares
double billing-Juliet,
Cleopatra. By
contrast,
in
extant Greek drama
women
often lend their
individual names
or
collective
functions
to the titles
(Antigone,
Elec-
tra,
Medea; Choephoroi,
Trachiniae, Bacchae,
etc.).
Moreover,
women
play
far
more
extensive
roles
in
Greek
tragedy,
which
increase
in
subtlety
and
variety
as
the
genre
develops.
15.
The functional argument
is even more
obviously
true
in
the case of those
plays
which
I
will
not
discuss
in this
essay,
in
which the
plot
revolves around the
demand made
upon
an
army
for a
virgin
sacrifice
(such
as
Iphigenia
and
Polyxena)
and
where female
heroic
nobility
in
dying
is
used
most often
to offer an
ironic
counterpoint
to
masculine
Realpolitik.
90
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
16. See
especially
B. M. W
Knox,
"TheMedea of
Euripides:'
Yale Classical
Studies
25 (1977):
198-225,
for
the discussion
of Medea's "imitation"
of male heroic
traits.
17. It
should be
stressed that
I equate
drama
here with
serious drama
rather
than with
comic
types
such as satyr
play and
comedy
itself, whose
primitive
elements
may
well
have
preceded
the growth
of the strange
mutant
that
is
tragedy. For
even if
we renounce
any hopes
of reconstructing
a
plausible
story
of origins, there
seems no
doubt
that
the tragic play
is
the first to achieve
the status
of art and
that
the other
forms only
follow subsequently
in
its wake
and under
its influence.
To
speak
of
theater
then
is
to speak
first
of
tragedy.
18.
Y. Belaval,
"Ouverture
sur le
spectacle,"
in Histoire des
spectacles,
ed. R. Queneau
(Paris,
1965),
3-16, esp. 8.
19.
I
have profited
from the
discussion
in the unpublished
paper of
Nicole Loraux,
"Ways
of
Killing
Women
in
Greek
Tragedy,"
who
views Ajax'
suicide as
an unequivocal
war-
rior's death.
It is true,
of
course,
that the
sword is a man's weapon
and
that
if
women
resort
to it,
it is they who
are violating
the
rules of gender.
Yet it
is also true
that Ajax'
death, by
whatever
means and
in
whatever
mood,
is
still a
suicide,
an
act
the culture
regards
in
itself
as inherently
shameful
and
therefore
imagined
far more as
a feminine
solution.
20.
On the
general
question
of the
female body
as the
model of
male
suffering,
see
the
superb
study
of Nicole
Loraux,
"Le
Lit,
la
guerre,"
L'Homme
21
(1981):
36-67.
For
these
symptoms
in
the
Hippolytus,
see
respectively
Loraux,
"Le
Lit"'
58-59,
and
Charles
Segal,
"The
Tragedy
of the
Hippolytus:
The Waters
of
Ocean and the Untouched
Meadow,"
Harvard Studies
in Classical
Philology
70
(1965):
117-69, esp.
122.
21.
See the discussion
of this remarkable
passage
and its key function
in the play
in
Zeitlin,
"The Power
of
Aphrodite:'
68-74.
22.
On Pandora in
the
Hesiodic
text,
see
especially
the fine
analyses
by Jean-Pierre
Ver-
nant, "The
Myth
of Prometheus
in
Hesiod,"
in Myth
and Society,
168-85;
and Nicole
Loraux, "Sur
la race
des femmes
et quelques-unes
de ses tribus,"
Arethusa
11
(1978):
43-88 (collected
in
her Les Enfants
d'Athena: Idves
atheniennes
sur
la
citoyennet6
et la
division
des
sexes
[Paris,
1981], 75
-117).
23.
It is worth
noting
too that
the details of the sacrifice
of the
virgin's
body
holds
par-
ticular fascination
for the messenger
speeches
of the
relevant
tragedies.
24.
See further
Ruth
Padel,
"Women: Model
for Possession
by
Greek
Daemons,"
in
Images
of
Women in
Antiquity,
ed. Averil Cameron
and
Amelie
Kuhrt
(London,
1983),
3-19.
It is
remarkable
that
in
Euripides'
Heracles,
where
the great Heracles
goes
mad and
kills his
wife and
children,
the chorus
in
response
compares
him
only with
women:
the Danaids (who
slew their husbands
on their wedding night)
and
Procne (who slew
her
child in
revenge
for
her
husband's
rape and
mutilation of
her sister,
Philomela;
Heracles
1016-27).
25.
On
the uses
of
these
stage
conventions
and their
relations
of the
inside/outside,
see
especially
A. M.
Dale,
"Seen
and
Unseen
on the Greek
Stage:"
in
Collected Papers
(Cambridge,
1969),
119-29;
the
discussion
of Padel, "Women";
and
Zeitlin,
"The
Power
of
Aphrodite:'
74-79.
26.
The
locus classicus
is
Xenophon's
Qeconomicus.
The
best
discussion
is
Jean-Pierre
Ver-
nant,
"Hestia-Hermes:
Sur l'expression
religieuse
de
l'espace et
du mouvement
chez
les
Grecs,"
in
Mythe
et
pensee
chez
les Grecs (Paris,
1965),
6-27.
27.
See,
for
example,
the
incisive
remarks of
Jean-Pierre
Vernant,
"Tensions and Ambi-
guities
in
Greek
Tragedy,"
in
Vernant and
Vidal-Naquet,
Myth and
Tragedy,
6-27. This
Playing
the
Other
91
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
epistemological emphasis
therefore both exploits and is conditioned by
the special
capacity of theater to
represent and embody the interaction between
other points of
view, attitudes, gestures, and
language.
28.
On
the
symbolic
value
of
the
house,
see
J. Wohlberg,
"The Palace-Hero
Equation
in
Euripides,"
Acta
Antiqua
Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae 16 (1968): 149
-
55; and the
much fuller discussion
in
Segal, Dionysiac Poetics, 86-94 and passim.
29.
For fuller discussion of these terms and their relation to the
structures and
structuring
capacities of plots, see
Zeitlin,
"The Power
of
Aphrodite:" 58-64.
30.
Jean-Pierre Vernant, "Intimations
of
the
Will
in
Greek
Tragedy,"
in
Myth
and Society,
51.
His is
the most nuanced
discussion of this
double determination
that
is
often
misnamed as a conflict between
fate and
free will.
31.
For discussions
of
intrigue
plots
in
general, see especially Friedrich
Solmsen, "Zur
Gestaltung
des
Intriguenmotivs
in
den
Tragodien
des
Sophokles
und
Euripides,'
Philologus 84 (1932): 1-17; and Hans
Strohm, "Trug
und
Tauschung
in
der euripi-
deischen Dramatik,"
Wiirzburger Jahrbucher fur
die
Altertum-swissenschaft
4
(1949/50):
140-56, collected
in
Euripides,
ed. E.
Schwinge, Wege
der
Forschung,
no.
89
(Darm-
stadt, 1968) as 326-44 and
345-72, respectively.
See now also the
wider-ranging
discussion
of
Frances
Muecke,
"'I
Know
You-By
Your
Rags':
Costume
and
Disguise
in
Fifth-Century Drama,"
Antichthon 16
(1982):
17-34.
32.
The Ion
of
Euripides,
a
play
in
many ways
a
precursor
of New
Comedy,
foils
the
woman's plot against her
unrecognized
son
(not without some fancy
help from the
gods) so as to bring about
the
joyful
reunion. The
play,
I
might add,
is
careful not to
credit the woman Creusa as the
one who first initiates the intrigue.
33.
Euripides'
Electra is
still more
complex,
as
the play separates the two acts of
vengeance
against Clytemnestra
and her
lover, Aegisthus.
The old
servant
suggests the plot
against Aegisthus (to
take
place
outside far
away
from
the house), while
Electra
con-
trives
the
elaborate and
doubly
deceitful
intrigue against Clytemnestra.
34. This
is
a
commonplace
in
tragic
texts
(as elsewhere): e.g., Iphigenia
in
Tauris
1032;
Medea
834-35;
Andromache
85; Hippolytus 480-81;
Ion
483.
35.
Even
in
these
plays,
masculine
honor is
protected,
as it
were,
in
that
each man
(Orestes,
Menelaus)
first
proposes
force
before he accedes to the
woman's
practical,
clever
schemes
(Iphigenia, Helen),
and
each, just
before
the
end,
is
permitted a
display
of
manly strength against
the
forces
of
the
barbarian
king
in
question.
36.
The one
exception
that
comes to mind
is
Euripides' strange play,
Andromache,
where
Orestes,
not a
major
character, successfully plots
to have
Neoptolemus
killed
at
Delphi
so
as to reclaim
the
latter's
wife, Hermione,
for his
own.
37.
"The covert theme
of
all
drama:' Michael Goldman
suggests,
"is
identificaton,
the
establishment
of
a
self
that
in
some
way
transcends the
confusions
of
self";
The Actors
Freedom:
Toward
a
Theory of
Drama
(New York, 1975), 123.
In
general,
I
have
learned
much from this
stimulating
study
of
the
workings
of
theater.
38.
Odysseus
is
the
exemplar
in the
masculine
sphere,
but he neither
generically repre-
sents "the
race
of men"
nor,
let
me
repeat,
is
this
adaptable
survivor
(with
strong
affinities,
in
fact,
to the
feminine)
a candidate
for
tragedy
in
the
dramatic milieu.
39.
Earlier
I
alluded
to the creation
of
Pandora as
exemplifying
the
physical,
"creaturely"
side
of life.
I
emphasize
now the other
aspect
of
woman's
creation
as an
object
cun-
ningly wrought;
she
is
a
deceptive gift
in
return
for
Prometheus'
deception
of
Zeus,
herself endowed with a
crafty
intelligence.
Woman therefore embodies
both extremes
of
nature and
culture
that
together conspire
to waste
a man's substance and
dry
him
up
before
his
time.
92
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
40. For a similar idea, see Ann
Bergren, "Language
and the Female
in
Early
Greek
Thought," Arethusa 16 (1983):
74,
77.
41. This is a combined quote
and paraphrase (with
one
small
alteration)
of
Bamber,
Comic
Women, Tragic Men,
15.
42. In this
respect,
there are
strong
continuities with the earlier
epic
tradition. See the
interesting conclusions of Helene
Monsacre's fine,
nuanced study,
Les Larmes
d'Achille:
Le
Heros,
la femme et la souffrance
dans la poesie
d'Homkre
(Paris,
1984), 199-204.
43. We might note that initiation
into the "real"
Eleusinian
mysteries
involved some
forms
of
imitating the specifically
feminine experiences
of
Demeter
and Kore.
44. More accurately, it is one
of the very last, produced posthumously
in
Athens as was
the
Iphigenia
in Aulis.
45. For the interplay of illusion
and reality, see Friedrich Solmsen,
"Onoma and Pragma
in
Euripides' Helen," Classical
Review 48 (1934): 119-21;
Ann
Pippin (Burnett), "Eurip-
ides' Helen:
A
Comedy
of Ideas," Classical Philology 55 (1960):
151-63; Charles Segal,
"The Two Worlds of Euripides'
Helen," Transactions of the
American Philological
Associ-
ation
102 (1971):
553-614; and see
now
George Walsh,
The Varieties
of
Enchantment:
Early Greek Views
on
the
Nature and Function of Poetry (Chapel
Hill, N.C., 1984),
96
-106.
On
the connections with
theater and femininity
in
the
context
of comic
parody,
see
Zeitlin, "Gender and
Genre," 186
-
89.
46.
I
simplify here the terms
of
the debate.
Both
sides
are
thoroughly
satirized
in
this
brilliant parody.
For
an
excellent discussion,
see
Walsh,
Varieties
of Enchantment,
80
-
97.
47.
See
especally Republic
595c, 598d,
605c-d,
607a,
602b.
48.
Republic 2.366a-b;
cf.
361b-c.
Strictly speaking,
the
Aeschylean quotes precede
the
discussion
of
the
mimetic
arts
in
book
3,
but their misuse
may
not
be fortuitous.
49.
I
include
in
the discussion
the relevant
portions
of
Republic,
Gorgias,
and
Laws,
to
be
followed by the Symposium.
50. This
issue deserves
far
more attention than space permits
here.
51.
Tragedy
is
the real
target,
despite
the
remarks about epic
poetry
and
comedy.
See
especially Laws 8 16d-e,
935d-
936b
for comedy, and 81 7a-d
for tragedy, where Plato
expressly sets up the legislators
as authors
of
their own true tragedies as "rivals
...
artists and actors
of
the
fairest
drama."
52.
One
single exception
is the woman
(wife
and
mother)
as
instigating
in her son
the
slide toward timocratic behavior
by her nagging and greed (Republic
549c-e). We will
take
up
the function
in
the
Symposium
of
the
priestess,
Diotima,
in
the
appropriate
context.
53.
The ostensible motive
for banning poets
in
book
3 is
the
education of the young
guardians
to
protect
the
city. Courage
in
battle
is
the
model for
control over
warring
forces
within the self,
as
is
emphasized
in
the second discussion of
imitation
in book
10.
Cowardice
is the
radically
feminine
trait, despite Plato's
willingness
to
train selected
women
as guardians. (The
locus classicus
is
Timaeus
90e-91a,
in which
Plato
describes
the first creation
of
women
as
due to
"creatures
generated
as
men
who
proved
them-
selves cowardly and spent
their
lives in
wrongdoing and were
transformed at their
second
incarnation into
women.")
I
simplify Plato's intricate
argument, as he further
sees this lack
of
control
over the emotions, engendered by
tragedy, as leading to an
unruliness and violence he does not specify as feminine. Yet
the tyrannical man, the
most
"theatrical"
in
Plato's
view, whose exterior pomp and
costume does not at all
match
his
inner self (Republic
577b), is seen ultimately as a
slave to his passions who
becomes so
fearful that
he "lives for the
most part cowering
in
the house like a woman"
(Republic 579b-c).
Playing
the
Other
93
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
54. In particular, the discussion would benefit from including
the important contribution
made by Alcibiades, the disruptive latecomer and
party crasher, but it would not in
any case substantially alter my argument.
55. In this comedy, which satirizes Euripidean tragedy
through the women's indignation
at the poet for his unflattering (and oversexed) portraits
of them, Agathon comes off
as the truly effeminate male by contrast to the trickster
but more manly figure
of
Euripides. Agathon appears
in
feminine accessories,
claiming that to write female
parts
for
the theater
one must
dress as a woman.
He
refuses
to
infiltrate
the women's
festival on the
grounds
that he would
provide
unfair competition
for
the "real" women,
and
finally supplies
the feminine costume for Euripides' kinsman,
who has been
persuaded to go
instead.
56.
Aristophanes presents the famous myth
of
the spherical
human beings who, separated
by Zeus
for
their hybris toward the gods, are
forever searching for reunion with their
other halves. These may
be of
the same
or
opposite
sex, depending on the original
composition of each.
94
REPRESENTATIONS
This content downloaded from 140.233.185.52 on Thu, 16 Jan 2014 14:04:49 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions