1783
IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE
FOUNDING
Jonathan Gienapp*
I
NTRODUCTION
At the American founding, the nation was an idea and, constitutionally
speaking, an immensely important one. Yet, it has been easy to ignore or
overlook. Sometimes its existence is taken for granted without much
additional reflection. The nation was simply proclaimed by the Declaration
of Independence and then realized through the war with Great Britain,
thereafter an undeniable reality.
1
Or, at other times, it has been assumed that
the American Revolution failed to produce a nation, at least not a real one
anyway.
2
Rather than creating a genuine nation-state, drawing on their
colonial past, the revolutionaries erected a confederacy of autonomous states,
held together by a “peace pact” or “federal treaty.”
3
By the terms of this
treaty, independent states confederated to project strength outward and
minimize interstate conflict without surrendering their essential sovereign
prerogatives.
4
While the impotent Confederation government managed
diplomacy, the real work of polity building that followed independence lay
with the states, which jealously guarded their corporate identities,
independent powers, and sovereign rights.
5
Even if the federal Constitution
* Assistant Professor of History, Stanford University. This Article was prepared for the
Symposium entitled The Federalist Constitution, hosted by the Fordham Law Review on
October 2, 2020, at Fordham University School of Law. For helpful feedback and suggestions,
I thank Jud Campbell, Martin Flaherty, Daniel J. Hulsebosch, Thomas Lee, Bernie Meyler,
John Mikhail, Jim Pfander, Richard Primus, and David Schwartz. For exceptional research
assistance, I thank Julia Milani.
1. On the Declaration of Independence as principally a statement of nationhood, see
generally D
AVID ARMITAGE, THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE: A GLOBAL HISTORY
(2007).
2. See D
AVID C. HENDRICKSON, PEACE PACT: THE LOST WORLD OF THE AMERICAN
FOUNDING ix–x, xiv, 257–58 (2003); Jack P. Greene, Colonial History and National History:
Reflections on a Continuing Problem, 64 W
M. & MARY Q. 235, 242–50 (2007); Peter S. Onuf,
A Declaration of Independence for Diplomatic Historians, 22 D
IPLOMATIC HIST. 71, 71–72,
79–83 (1998).
3. See generally H
ENDRICKSON, supra note 2; Max M. Edling, Peace Pact and Nation:
An International Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States, 240 P
AST & PRESENT
267 (2018).
4. See Edling, supra note 3, at 281–83; see also H
ENDRICKSON, supra note 2, at 24–29,
104–11, 125–26, 145–46; Greene, supra note 2, at 242–43; Onuf, supra note 2, at 72–73, 76–
78.
5. See J
ACK P. GREENE, PERIPHERIES AND CENTER: CONSTITUTIONAL DEVELOPMENT IN
THE
EXTENDED POLITIES OF THE BRITISH EMPIRE AND THE UNITED STATES, 1607–1788, at 172–
1784 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
of 1787 marked a remaking of the state-centered order, it did not
fundamentally change—nor seek to change—the original purpose or aims of
the original confederation.
6
The American states joined in a perpetual union
and empowered a central government to promote the common defense,
manage diplomacy, and regulate international trade but not to meddle in
domestic matters—those would remain firmly within the province of the
states, which is ultimately where most citizens’ true loyalties lay.
7
The early
United States, thus, more closely resembled a states system than a nation-
state.
8
Only much later would this conception of federal union give way to
the idea of a unitary American nation.
9
While no doubt many founding-era Americans viewed the Union in such
diffuse terms and while, practically speaking, the Union might well have
functioned in such a decentralized manner, we should not overlook why some
revolutionaries—especially those who would become leading
Federalists
10
—invested so much energy trying to establish the nation’s
80 (1986); MERRILL JENSEN, THE ARTICLES OF CONFEDERATION: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE
SOCIAL-CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY OF THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION, 1774–1781, at 14–15,
109–10, 161–76, 239–45 (1970);
GORDON S. WOOD, THE CREATION OF THE AMERICAN
REPUBLIC 1776–1787, at 127–34, 355–59, 463–67 (2d ed. 1998).
6. Edling, supra note 3, at 284–91; see also HENDRICKSON, supra note 2, at xiv, 3–7,
242–48, 257–59; Anthony J. Bellia Jr. & Bradford R. Clark, The International Law Origins
of American Federalism, 120 C
OLUM. L. REV. 835, 857–71 (2020); Daniel H. Deudney, The
Philadelphian System: Sovereignty, Arms Control, and Balance of Power in the American
States-Union, Circa 1787–1861, 49 I
NTL ORG. 191, 194–216 (1995); Greene, supra note 2,
at 243–45; Onuf, supra note 2, at 78–83; Robbie J. Totten, Security, Two Diplomacies, and
the Formation of the U.S. Constitution: Review, Interpretation, and New Directions for the
Study of the Early American Period, 36 D
IPLOMATIC HIST. 77, 77–80, 89–110 (2012); Michael
P. Zuckert, Federalism and the Founding: Toward a Reinterpretation of the Constitutional
Convention, 48 R
EV. POL. 166, 174–75 (1986). See generally AARON N. COLEMAN, THE
AMERICAN REVOLUTION, STATE SOVEREIGNTY, AND THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL
SETTLEMENT, 1765–1800 (2016); FORREST MCDONALD, STATES RIGHTS AND THE UNION:
IMPERIUM IN IMPERIO, 1776–1876 (2000); PETER ONUF & NICHOLAS ONUF, FEDERAL UNION,
MODERN WORLD: THE LAW OF NATIONS IN AN AGE OF REVOLUTIONS 1776–1814 (1993).
7. Edling, supra note 3, at 287. On the intellectual roots of American federalism, see
generally A
LISON L. LACROIX, THE IDEOLOGICAL ORIGINS OF AMERICAN FEDERALISM (2010).
On the lack of national identity at the time of the founding, see G
REENE, supra note 5, at 157–
65; F
ORREST MCDONALD, E PLURIBUS UNUM: THE FORMATION OF THE AMERICAN REPUBLIC,
1776–1790, at 17–18 (2d ed. 1979); John M. Murrin, A Roof Without Walls: The Dilemma of
American National Identity, in B
EYOND CONFEDERATION: ORIGINS OF THE CONSTITUTION AND
AMERICAN NATIONAL IDENTITY 333 (Richard Beeman et al. eds., 1987).
8. See H
ENDRICKSON, supra note 2, at ix–xii; Deudney, supra note 6, at 194, 208–09,
222; Totten, supra note 6, at 79–80, 111, 113–14.
9. See H
ENDRICKSON, supra note 2, at 281–97.
10. In this Article, for convenience, I mostly use the terms “Federalist” and “nationalist”
interchangeably. At times, though, I hint at the ways in which they picked out distinct groups
of individuals at the founding. “Federalists” could describe both those who supported the
Constitution’s ratification and members of the nascent political party that took form over the
course of the subsequent decade that supported President George Washington’s administration
and Alexander Hamilton’s controversial financial plan. Some Federalists of the first variety,
such as James Madison, became leading opponents of the later Federalists. Most Federalists,
of either kind, were nationalists. But some were assuredly more committed to expansive
national power than were others, especially during ratification. When I use the term
“nationalists,” I do so to refer either to those individuals who championed increasing the power
of the national government prior to the Constitutional Convention (and thus, before the term
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1785
existence. Leading Federalists, many of whom played as significant a role
in creating the Constitution as anybody, fervently rejected the idea that the
Constitutional Convention had created a mere treaty. This was no modest
quibble over names or forms, either. The difference between the
Constitution, as they imagined it, and a treaty was vast and significant.
Constitutionally and legally speaking, few differences mattered more.
Federalists’ search for nationhood—as well as its implications and
consequences—thus deserves further attention. Understanding why they
conducted this intellectual work and how successfully they grounded their
claims in commonly held assumptions illuminates an obscured dimension of
founding-era constitutional thinking. It gives us new reason to emphasize
the importance of nationhood at the founding and to not be so quick to
assume that devolved federalism and localism were the shared commitments
of the day.
In various ways, scholars have already helped point us in this direction. A
recent wave of important work has called attention to the neglected
importance of early American nationhood and constitutional governance.
11
Some have stressed that the ostensibly weak national government was
actually far stronger and more capable than previously assumed.
12
Others
have shown how, following ratification of the Constitution, state and federal
centralization were not at odds but worked in tandem, as national authority
helped states concentrate their power.
13
Still others have demonstrated
powerfully how Federalists’ pursuit of international recognition led them to
emphasize the legal foundation of nationhood.
14
What also deserves
Federalist had emerged) or, alternatively, to those Federalists who most energetically
championed a powerful national government. See STANLEY ELKINS & ERIC MCKITRICK, THE
AGE OF FEDERALISM: THE EARLY AMERICAN REPUBLIC, 1788–1800, at 21–24 (1993)
(discussing the differences between early and later Federalism). See generally David M.
Golove & Daniel J. Hulsebosch, A Civilized Nation: The Early American Constitution, the
Law of Nations, and the Pursuit of International Recognition, 85 N.Y.U.
L. REV. 932 (2010)
(describing how leading Federalists at this time were strong nationalists).
11. For a comprehensive overview, see generally Gautham Rao, The New Historiography
of the Early Federal Government: Institutions, Contexts, and the Imperial State, 77 W
M. &
MARY Q. 97 (2020).
12. See generally G
REGORY ABLAVSKY, FEDERAL GROUND: GOVERNING PROPERTY AND
VIOLENCE IN THE FIRST U.S. TERRITORIES (2021); BRIAN BALOGH, A GOVERNMENT OUT OF
SIGHT: THE MYSTERY OF NATIONAL AUTHORITY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY AMERICA (2009);
M
AX M. EDLING, A HERCULES IN THE CRADLE: WAR, MONEY, AND THE AMERICAN STATE,
1783–1867 (2014); RICHARD R. JOHN, SPREADING THE NEWS: THE AMERICAN POSTAL SYSTEM
FROM
FRANKLIN TO MORSE (1995); JERRY L. MASHAW, CREATING THE ADMINISTRATIVE
CONSTITUTION: THE LOST ONE HUNDRED YEARS OF AMERICAN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW (2012);
G
AUTHAM RAO, NATIONAL DUTIES: CUSTOMS HOUSES AND THE MAKING OF THE AMERICAN
STATE (2016); LINDSAY SCHAKENBACH REGELE, MANUFACTURING ADVANTAGE: WAR, THE
STATE, AND THE ORIGINS OF AMERICAN INDUSTRY, 1776–1848 (2019); Andrew J. B. Fagal,
American Arms Manufacturing and the Onset of the War of 1812, 87 N
EW ENG. Q. 526 (2014);
Richard R. John, Governmental Institutions as Agents of Change: Rethinking American
Political Development in the Early Republic, 1787–1835, 11 S
TUD. AM. POL. DEV. 347 (1997).
13. See generally Gregory Ablavsky, Empire States: The Coming of Dual Federalism,
128 Y
ALE L.J. 1792 (2019).
14. See generally ELIGA H. GOULD, AMONG THE POWERS OF THE EARTH: THE AMERICAN
REVOLUTION AND THE MAKING OF A NEW WORLD EMPIRE (2012); Golove & Hulsebosch, supra
1786 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
attention is how defenses of national power were imagined and justified at
the founding. On this front, several scholars have begun to underscore key
facets of early nationalist constitutionalism that have long been downplayed
or ignored, facets that point to a robust and ascendant Federalist Constitution
in the nation’s earliest years that seriously disrupts the enduring portrait of
the period’s constitutionalism.
15
To further flesh out this Federalist Constitution that recent scholarship has
begun to bring back into view, I focus on one particularly vital argument that
founding-era nationalists relied on: that the existence of a national social
contract entitled the national government to expansive power. Leading
politicians and jurists, such as Alexander Hamilton, James Wilson, John Jay,
John Adams, Gouverneur Morris, Rufus King, and Fisher Ames, made
creative use of social contract theory, tapping into what was, at the time, a
ubiquitous intellectual resource—that otherwise provided a pervasive
framework for understanding the nature of political society and the
foundations of constitutional authority—and turning it to their advantage.
While scholars of the founding have long attended to the place of social
contract theory in revolutionary American political and constitutional
discourse, they have almost always interpreted it as a mechanism for
note 10; Daniel J. Hulsebosch, Being Seen Like a State: How Americans (and Britons) Built
the Constitutional Infrastructure of a Developing Nation, 59 W
M. & MARY L. REV. 1239
(2018); Daniel J. Hulsebosch, The Revolutionary Portfolio: Constitution-Making and the
Wider World in the American Revolution, 47 S
UFFOLK U. L. REV. 759 (2014).
15. See generally, e.g., Jack M. Balkin, Commerce, 109 M
ICH. L. REV 1 (2010); Jonathan
Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given: Enumeration and National Power at the
Founding, 69 A
M. U. L. REV. F. 183 (2020) [hereinafter Gienapp, The Myth of the
Constitutional Given]; Jonathan Gienapp, National Power and the Presidency: Rival Forms
of Federalist Constitutionalism at the Founding, in P
OLITICAL THOUGHT AND THE ORIGINS OF
THE
AMERICAN PRESIDENCY 127 (Ben Lowe ed. 2021) [hereinafter Gienapp, National Power
and the Presidency]; Calvin H. Johnson, The Dubious Enumerated Power Doctrine, 22
C
ONST. COMMENT. 25 (2005); Robert J. Kaczorowski, Inherent National Sovereignty
Constitutionalism: An Original Understanding of the U.S. Constitution, 101 M
INN. L. REV.
699 (2016); John Mikhail, The Constitution and the Philosophy of Language: Entailment,
Implicature, and Implied Powers, 101 V
A. L. REV. 1063 (2015) [hereinafter Mikhail, The
Constitution and the Philosophy of Language]; John Mikhail, The Necessary and Proper
Clauses, 102 G
EO. L.J. 1045 (2014) [hereinafter Mikhail, The Necessary and Proper Clauses];
Richard Primus, Herein of “Herein Granted”: Why Article I’s Vesting Clause Does Not
Support the Doctrine of Enumerated Powers, 35 C
ONST. COMMENT. 301 (2020); Richard
Primus, The Essential Characteristic”: Enumerated Powers and the Bank of the United
States, 117 M
ICH. L. REV. 415 (2018); Richard Primus, The Limits of Enumeration, 124 YALE
L.J. 576 (2014); Richard Primus, Why Enumeration Matters, 115 MICH. L. REV. 1 (2016);
Robert J. Reinstein, The Aggregate and Implied Powers of the United States, 69 A
M. U. L.
REV. 3 (2019); David S. Schwartz, A Question Perpetually Arising: Implied Powers, Capable
Federalism, and the Limits of Enumerationism, 59 A
RIZ. L. REV. 573 (2017); David S.
Schwartz, McCulloch v. Maryland and the Incoherence of Enumerationism, 19 G
EO. J.L. &
PUB. POLY (forthcoming 2021), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract
_id=3535750 [https://perma.cc/VV45-SSFZ]; David S. Schwartz, Recovering the Lost
General Welfare Clause (Univ. of Wis. L. Sch. Legal Stud. Rsch. Paper Series No. 1603,
2021), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3671883 [https://perma.cc/LAB2
-NUF6].
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1787
protecting rights and limiting government power.
16
Only rarely have
scholars considered how social contract thinking helped expand
governmental authority based on what it revealed about the interconnected
implications of sovereignty, polity formation, and constitutional power. Yet,
in the hands of early nationalists, this was one of social contract theory’s most
vital roles.
At the founding, Federalists contended that there was a tight, inextricable
relationship between the nature of the federal union and the character and
scope of governmental power—that the latter could not be understood apart
from the former. If, as a matter of legal fact, the United States was a nation,
then its government enjoyed a credible claim to more power than might
otherwise be assumed. If, however, the United States was not a nation, then
its government necessarily was entitled to less power. What the Constitution
permitted was determined, to a meaningful extent, by the nature of the
underlying polity. In the early years of the republic, to an extent that is rarely
appreciated, this argument held a tight grip on constitutional thinking. Not
only did nationalists champion the idea but, arguably even more importantly,
their opponents fully recognized its power. Precisely because Federalists
built their account of national authority on such an authoritative foundation,
and precisely because their starting point enjoyed such broad resonance
across ideological divisions, their arguments had a clear impact on their
intellectual and political rivals. These opponents recognized that defeating
the Federalist account of national power meant undermining their attendant
account of the social contract. Not everybody agreed with the Federalists
that the United States was a nation, but most everybody agreed on why that
fact was constitutionally important.
This dimension of Federalist constitutionalism and the ways in which it
resonated in the early republic are curiously neglected. We know a great deal
about debates during this period over nationhood, the contested nature of the
federal union, social contract theory, and popular sovereignty. We know far
less, however, about the ways in which each of these debates was
interconnected—how a particular account of the national social contract
bolstered a broad conception of national power. The burden of what follows
is to bring these connections and the once pervasive, if now less familiar,
kinds of constitutional arguments that they yielded back into focus in order
to underscore their original significance. They illuminate a now forgotten
16. See generally, e.g., SCOTT DOUGLAS GERBER, TO SECURE THESE RIGHTS: THE
DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE AND CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION (1995); THOMAS L.
PANGLE, THE SPIRIT OF MODERN REPUBLICANISM: THE MORAL VISION OF THE AMERICAN
FOUNDERS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOCKE (1988); C. BRADLEY THOMPSON, AMERICAS
REVOLUTIONARY MIND: A MORAL HISTORY OF THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION AND THE
DECLARATION THAT DEFINED IT (2019); THOMAS G. WEST, THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE
AMERICAN FOUNDING: NATURAL RIGHTS, PUBLIC POLICY, AND THE MORAL CONDITIONS OF
FREEDOM (2017); MICHAEL P. ZUCKERT, THE NATURAL RIGHTS REPUBLIC: STUDIES IN THE
FOUNDATION OF THE AMERICAN POLITICAL TRADITION (1996); Philip A. Hamburger, Natural
Rights, Natural Law, and American Constitutions, 102 Y
ALE L.J. 907 (1993).
1788 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
way of thinking about constitutionalism that was once inextricably
intertwined with the original Constitution.
This Article proceeds as follows. Part I examines social contract theory,
considering the ways in which it is often misunderstood. Rather than simply
placing limits on government power, at the founding, this form of thinking
helped empower government to act in the general welfare. Parts II and III
discuss how founding-era nationalists leveraged social contract theory to
support their expansive vision of national power up through the drafting of
the federal Constitution. Part IV investigates how, during ratification,
Federalists and anti-Federalists debated what the proposed Constitution
implied about the nature of the federal union. Part V demonstrates how
readily Federalists, following ratification, claimed that debates over national
power under the Constitution ultimately turned on the character of the United
States itself. Part VI shows how Republicans, despite sharply disagreeing
with Federalists’ conclusions about national power, nonetheless agreed with
their guiding premise: that the national government’s authority was
determined by the kind of polity it represented. Ultimately, whether or not
the United States was a nation made a decisive difference. From the
standpoint of constitutionalism, Federalists effectively argued that the scope
of the national government’s power was a function of the kind of union it
governed. And remarkably, to an extent seldom appreciated, their opponents
agreed. The concept of nationhood was central to founding-era constitutional
thought and, if we seek to understand the original Constitution on its own
terms, we must understand why this was.
I.
SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY AT THE FOUNDING
Federalists’ interest in nationhood owed a great deal to how they thought
about polity formation and the origins of the social compact—the underlying
foundations of the constitutional regime. It was here that social contract
theory played such a foundational role in their arguments.
Understanding how requires first appreciating what prior study of this
subject has missed. There is, of course, nothing novel in claiming that social
contract thinking—which was utterly ubiquitous in early modern European
political theory—informed Revolutionary-era American political thought.
17
Yet, virtually all attention that has been paid to this kind of founding-era
thinking has focused on the protection of individual rights or the cordoning
off of certain spheres of liberty and thus on limitations on government
power.
18
Social contract theory was built on a thought experiment designed
to understand why human beings would have left a hypothetical state of
nature, in which they enjoyed natural liberty, for the protections of
government.
19
People would have done so, students of this theory often
17. See, e.g., supra note 16 and accompanying text.
18. See supra note 16 and accompanying text.
19. Jud Campbell, Republicanism and Natural Rights at the Founding, 32 C
ONST.
COMMENT. 85, 87–88 (2017) (reviewing RANDY E. BARNETT, OUR REPUBLICAN
CONSTITUTION: SECURING THE LIBERTY AND SOVEREIGNTY OF WE THE PEOPLE 31–82 (2016)).
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1789
emphasize, to ensure protection of their individual natural rights.
20
Government, therefore, is best understood as a contract predicated on
consent—a bargain made to sacrifice some liberty to ensure that the
remainder is safely guarded.
21
By these terms, government power is
inherently constrained and limited, and its exercise is to be watched with
relentless suspicion. In short, on this view, social contract theory offered an
account of limited government. Hardly any attention, however, has been
given to the ways in which, in the hands of certain founding-era Americans,
social contract thinking served to expand government power.
22
This is an
oversight that both misses the thrust of social contract theory at the founding
and the far-reaching uses to which some leading founders put it.
Analyses of founding-era social contract thinking have often narrowly
focused on rights and limitations to government power because, too often,
they are infected with anachronism. They tend to be tacitly guided by the
modern libertarian presumption that liberty and state power are inherently at
odds—locked in a zero-sum game.
23
Where government acts, liberty is
threatened, meaning the state should strive to do the minimum necessary to
maintain order and the rule of law without interfering with the retained rights
of consenting citizens—who only would have parted with certain kinds of
natural liberty to secure the reliance and consistency that regular legal order
alone could provide.
24
This is why the founding generation purportedly
conceived of rights as trumps against the government.
25
No matter how
popular these assumptions are today or how frequently they are imposed on
the founding, they would have made little sense in the eighteenth century.
At that time, power and liberty were not believed to be inherently at odds.
To be sure, it was widely assumed that liberty was fragile and always under
threat and that unchecked, tyrannical power was always quick to destroy it.
26
However, one protected liberty not by disabling government power but rather
by empowering government in the right kind of way. This meant, above all,
constructing representative institutions that, by embodying the people’s will,
protected the people’s liberty.
27
There was, in fact, no solution to the
problem of liberty other than robust political institutions.
20. See, e.g., ZUCKERT, supra note 16, at 24–31.
21. Id. at 27–29.
22. Jud Campbell’s work, which has done so much to illuminate social contract thinking
at the founding, is an important exception. Even so, Campbell has primarily focused on the
nature of rights at the founding and only gestured toward the ways in which some founders
harnessed social contract thinking to defend the robust exercise of government power. For
one of these brief forays, see Campbell, supra note 19, at 101–03, 109–11. My argument is
indebted to his analysis of eighteenth-century social contract thinking.
23. See B
ARNETT, supra note 19, at 31–82; RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, THE CLASSICAL LIBERAL
CONSTITUTION: THE UNCERTAIN QUEST FOR LIMITED GOVERNMENT 3–6, 17–25 (2014); Philip
Hamburger, The Inversion of Rights and Power, 63
BUFF. L. REV. 731, 738–52 (2015).
24. See B
ARNETT, supra note 19, at 31–82; EPSTEIN, supra note 23, at 3–6, 17–25.
25. Hamburger, supra note 23, at 752.
26. See generally B
ERNARD BAILYN, THE IDEOLOGICAL ORIGINS OF THE AMERICAN
REVOLUTION 55–93 (enlarged ed. 1992).
27. Jonathan Gienapp, Response, The Foreign Founding: Rights, Fixity, and the Original
Constitution, 97 T
EX. L. REV. ONLINE 115, 118–26 (2019). For the deeper colonial roots of
1790 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
In this regard, our familiar distinctions between individual and collective
liberty often had little meaning at the founding. Residents of the eighteenth
century surely would have recognized how those categories were distinct, but
they tended to think of them in compatible terms. One was not protected at
the expense or denial of the other; instead, protecting one often ensured the
protection of the other.
28
Individual and collective rights to a free press and
jury trial and to speak freely, assemble, and bear arms were most effectively
secured by devising and empowering popular institutions that promoted, all
at once, the people’s liberty, welfare, and happiness.
29
The crucial
distinction was not between government and liberty but between
representative government (which protected liberty) and unrepresentative
government (which did not). “Representation,” proclaimed Moses Mather
on the eve of the American Revolution, “is the feet upon which a free
government stands.”
30
Liberty was not the absence of coercion but a state of
being, predicated on living in a free state and, thus, the conditions of that
state being free.
31
Jud Campbell has compellingly demonstrated how
founding-era Americans reconciled their commitment to retained
fundamental rights and the power of republican governments to regulate
those rights in the interest of the public good.
32
The latter did not violate
commitment to the former; rather, it embodied the very essence of freedom.
33
Alexander Hamilton thus described the “great principle of the social
compact” to be “that the chief object of government is to protect the rights of
individuals by the united strength of the community.”
34
The primary reason
one studied natural rights and probed the origins of the social compact was
to identify the kind of government that could act most credibly in the public
interest.
35
As the town of Boston proclaimed in 1772, “[t]he natural Liberty
of Man, by entering into Society, is abridg’d or restrain’d so far only as is
necessary for the great End of Society, the best Good of the Whole.”
36
this thinking, see generally BARBARA CLARK SMITH, THE FREEDOMS WE LOST: CONSENT AND
RESISTANCE IN REVOLUTIONARY AMERICA (2010).
28. Gienapp, supra note 27, at 118–26.
29. Jud Campbell, Natural Rights and the First Amendment, 127 Y
ALE L.J. 246, 265–66,
272–87, 304–21 (2017).
30. M
OSES MATHER, AMERICAS APPEAL TO THE IMPARTIAL WORLD 70 (Hartford,
Ebenezer Watson 1775).
31. Gienapp, supra note 27, at 125–26. See generally Q
UENTIN SKINNER, LIBERTY BEFORE
LIBERALISM (1998) (recounting the development of this theory in seventeenth-century
England and exploring its impact on the early United States).
32. Campbell, supra note 29, at 265–66, 272–87, 304–21; Campbell, supra note 19, at
87–99, 111–12; Jud Campbell, The Invention of First Amendment Federalism, 97 T
EX. L. REV.
517, 525–29 (2019); Jud Campbell, Fundamental Rights at the American Founding 7–9 (Dec.
9, 2020) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with author).
33. J
OHN PHILLIP REID, THE ANCIENT CONSTITUTION AND THE ORIGINS OF ANGLO-
A
MERICAN LIBERTY 38–39 (2005).
34. New York Assembly. Remarks on an Act Acknowledging the Independence of
Vermont, D
AILY ADVERTISER (N.Y.), Apr. 5, 1787, reprinted in 4 THE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER
HAMILTON 126, 126 (Harold C. Syrett & Jacob E. Cooke eds., 1962).
35. See id.
36. T
HE VOTES AND PROCEEDINGS OF THE FREEHOLDERS AND OTHER INHABITANTS OF THE
TOWN OF BOSTON 4–5 (Boston Edes & Gill 1772) [hereinafter, VOTES AND PROCEEDINGS].
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1791
Given this unfamiliar understanding of the relationship between liberty
and power, social contract theory—although squarely focused on the
retention and protection of liberty and used to understand the origins of
political communities with just this aim in mind—had no trouble reconciling
what we would think of as limited and expansive government. Government
was limited through a variety of means, but none more important than
representation.
37
A government that was representative, and thus was
limited, could claim the power necessary to advance the public good—and,
indeed, often had a duty to do so.
38
In the context of the American founding,
social contract theory was, therefore, not simply or even primarily
preoccupied with curbing government power but rather focused on offering
a basis for the legitimate exercise of government power, thus realizing the
fundamental aim of republican political organization.
39
Because liberty was so entangled with representation, it mattered
enormously for whom the government spoke—whom it could claim to
embody and mirror.
40
Determining whom the government represented, and
thus could act in the name of to pursue the public good, invited consideration
of how the public related to its government. Here, social contract theory,
given how it conceived of the origins and nature of the political community,
provided potent answers.
Social contract theory furnished a conceptual framework for thinking
about the basis of governance. It imagined a two-step process in which
individuals formed, first, a social compact (a body politic) and then second,
a system of government (a constitution).
41
“The first ‘collection’ of
authority,” John Adams explained, was an “agreement” among individuals
“to form themselves into a nation, people, community, or body politic.”
42
Alexander Hamilton, in his 1775 pamphlet, The Farmer Refuted, claimed
similarly that “the origin of all civil government, justly established, must be
a voluntary compact.”
43
“When Men enter into Society,” declared the town
of Boston shortly before Americans declared independence, “by voluntary
37. See Campbell, supra note 19, at 96–98; Gienapp, supra note 27, at 125–26.
38. On the importance of the public good at the founding, see J
AMES T. KLOPPENBERG,
TOWARD DEMOCRACY: THE STRUGGLE FOR SELF-RULE IN EUROPEAN AND AMERICAN
THOUGHT 337–38, 349–55, 428–33 (2016); WOOD, supra note 5, at 53–65, 179–80.
39. Campbell, supra note 19, at 87–99, 111–12; Gienapp, supra note 27, at 118–26.
40. On the logic of political representation at the founding and how it often emphasized
the idea of mirroring or re-presenting the people at-large, see E
RIC NELSON, THE ROYALIST
REVOLUTION: MONARCHY AND THE AMERICAN FOUNDING 72–75, 78–83, 209–10 (2014); ERIC
SLAUTER, THE STATE AS A WORK OF ART: THE CULTURAL ORIGINS OF THE CONSTITUTION 123–
67 (2009). For characteristic statements from the founding, see J
OHN ADAMS, THOUGHTS ON
GOVERNMENT: APPLICABLE TO THE PRESENT STATE OF THE AMERICAN COLONIES 9–10
(Philadelphia, John Dunlap 1776); Brutus
III, N.Y.J., Nov. 15, 1787, reprinted in 14 THE
DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE
CONSTITUTION 119, 120–22 (John P. Kaminski et al. eds., 1983).
41. Campbell, supra note 19, at 87–90; Donald S. Lutz, From Covenant to Constitution
in American Political Thought, 10 P
UBLIUS 101, 103–06 (1980).
42. J
OHN ADAMS, A DEFENCE OF THE CONSTITUTIONS OF GOVERNMENT OF THE UNITED
STATES OF AMERICA 6 (Philadelphia, Hall & Sellers 1787).
43. A
LEXANDER HAMILTON, THE FARMER REFUTED 6 (New York, James Rivington 1775).
1792 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
Consent . . . [they] form an . . . original Compact.”
44
The Massachusetts
Constitution explicitly begins from this premise as well. Its preamble reads:
“The body-politic is formed by a voluntary association of individuals: It is a
social compact, by which the whole people covenants with each citizen, and
each citizen with the whole people, that all shall be governed by certain laws
for the common good.”
45
The social compact created a polity, the members
of which then decided on how they would be governed.
46
Step two followed. “The society being formed,” James Wilson elaborated
in his Lectures on Law, next came “the formation of [a] government.”
47
The
powers and obligations of the latter flowed from the constitution of the
former, because the body politic both established the government to act in its
name and retained sovereignty following that delegation.
48
When the
society was formed,” Wilson went on, “it possessed jointly all the previously
separate and independent powers and rights of the individuals who formed
it,” but it also obtained “all the other powers and rights, which result from
the social union.”
49
The “aggregate of . . . powers” that “compose[d] the
sovereignty of the society or nation”
50
was thus determined, in significant
measure, by the kind of union that had been formed.
51
Different social
compacts produced different sums of power that were delegated, in turn, to
the governments presiding over them.
52
A government’s power thus
reflected the nature of the sovereign agent that had given life to it.
53
Throughout the eighteenth century, different writers and commentators
reached different conclusions about the nature of the social contract, how its
conceptual pieces fit together, and its implications for political authority.
But, at the risk of oversimplification, most everybody at the founding agreed
on the outlines of the framework just sketched.
54
And in the hands of
nationalists in the 1780s—those who soon became Federalists and
spearheaded the movement for federal constitutional reform—this
framework held the potential for a dramatic expansion of national power.
44. VOTES AND PROCEEDINGS, supra note 36, at 3.
45. M
ASS. CONST. pmbl.
46. See id.
47. J
AMES WILSON, Lectures on Law, Part 2, Chapter V: Of Municipal Law, reprinted in
1 C
OLLECTED WORKS OF JAMES WILSON 549, 554 (Kermit L. Hall & Mark David Hall eds.,
2007).
48. See id. at 553–54.
49. Id. at 556.
50. Id.
51. See id.
52. See id.
53. Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given, supra note 15, at 201; Jud Campbell,
The Natures of Constitutional Histories, B
ALKINIZATION (May 1, 2020), https://balkin.
blogspot.com/2020/05/the-natures-of-constitutional-histories.html [https://perma.cc/H2FM-
242V].
54. See supra notes 41–53 and accompanying text.
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1793
II.
A NATIONAL PEOPLE, A NATIONAL POLITY: FINDING THE NATION
With social contract theory firmly in mind, leading nationalists would
come to argue that the full scope of national power under the Constitution
turned on sovereignty and union: who had authorized the Constitution and
for what kind of polity did that agent speak? The nature of the polity and the
meaning of the Constitution were inextricably entwined. Without
understanding the social compact (step one in social contract theory), it was
impossible to interpret the resulting constitution (step two). Depending on
the character of the union, the exact same constitutional provisions might
yield a different ambit of constitutional power. It was thus impossible to
know what the Constitution declared—and therefore licensed or prohibited—
without first understanding the nature of the federal union for which it spoke.
In the context of the United States, sorting out the character of the polity
and its attendant sovereignty was complicated by the federal nature of the
Union. There was wide agreement that the people were, in some manner,
sovereign. During the revolutionary struggle against Britain, Americans had
rallied around the concept of popular sovereignty; and then, during their
initial efforts to construct an independent constitutional order, they had
deepened and refined their understanding of it.
55
But, even as a matter of
constitutional theory, if it was clear that the people wielded sovereign
authority, in the context of authorizing a national government to preside over
the nascent American Union, it was much less clear which people delegated
the relevant authority: the people of the United States or the people of the
separate states. The answer determined whether the body politic was
rightfully understood to be a union of sovereign states, a nation, or something
in between. For those both committed and opposed to a stronger national
government, these were foundational questions—the ones that needed to be
answered in order to comprehend the full scope of the federal government’s
power: which kind of sovereign people had constituted the government and
which kind of polity did the Constitution speak for? Many Federalists would
come to defend an expansive vision of national power based on the belief
that the Constitution had been established by a national people who had
previously formed a national polity.
56
Nationalists began gesturing toward these conclusions throughout the
1780s as they decried and lamented the feeble state of the Union—
particularly the impotent state of the national government that struggled to
govern the country or address any of its mounting problems.
57
From these
complaints emerged not just calls for sweeping reform (which would
55. See WOOD, supra note 5, at 344–89, 445–46, 462–63 (offering the canonical account
of this concept). Of course, the accepted notion of the “people” at the time usually referred to
white men.
56. Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given, supra note 15, at 193–94, 201–04.
57. See generally M
ICHAEL J. KLARMAN, THE FRAMERS COUP: THE MAKING OF THE
UNITED STATES CONSTITUTION 11–125 (2016) (discussing the problems of the 1780s and the
criticisms of the Confederation government that they inspired); JACK N. RAKOVE, ORIGINAL
MEANINGS: POLITICS AND IDEAS IN THE MAKING OF THE CONSTITUTION 23–34 (1996) (same).
1794 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
eventually win converts toward the end of the decade)
58
but also creative
accounts of the nature of union, ones that claimed that the United States had
been born a nation.
59
In that regard, as soon-to-be Federalists at once called
for significant constitutional change, they also emphasized what they
believed already to be the case—that which demanded recognition and
acceptance, rather than invention: the idea that, through the act of
independence, the American people had formed a national social compact.
60
A genuine national government was needed not only to solve the problems
crippling the Union but also to affirm the kind of political community that
the Revolution had brought into existence: “an
INDEPENDENT NATION.”
61
As one of the earliest critics of the Confederation government and boldest
champions of national power, Alexander Hamilton was among the first to
suggest that, no matter the “want of power in Congress,”
62
thewant of
method and energy in the administration,”
63
or the myriad other ways in
which the Confederation was ill structured,
64
as a point of fact, the United
States government had “done many of the highest acts of sovereignty.”
65
Among the most vital of these—beyond declaring war, establishing an army
and navy, issuing money, making alliances with foreign powers, and forging
a peace treaty—was the “declaration of independence”—the act of deciding
that British Americans were an independent nation.
66
These feats of high
sovereignty implied that the national government had been vested, from the
58. See RAKOVE, supra note 57, at 23–34.
59. See, e.g., J
AMES WILSON, CONSIDERATIONS ON THE BANK OF NORTH-AMERICA 10
(Phila., Hall & Sellers 1785) (stating that, rather than enumerating the colonies separately, the
Declaration of Independence declared the colonies were “UNITED”).
60. As will be explained, Jeffersonian Republicans later developed their own theory of
the legal basis of the Union—a theory that they called “compact theory. See infra Part VI.
Although the terminology can be confusing, following the concepts and vocabulary of the
period is important. Americans of all ideological stripes, and especially Federalists, frequently
referred to the idea of a social compact by way of social contract theory. For a deeper
explanation and comparison of social contract theory to compact theory, see infra note 187
and accompanying text.
61. Alexander Hamilton, The Continentalist No. I, N.Y.
PACKET & AM. ADVERTISER, July
12, 1781, reprinted in 2 T
HE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note 34, at 649, 649.
62. Id. at 650 (emphasis omitted); Letter from Alexander Hamilton to James Duane (Sept.
3, 1780), in 2 T
HE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note 34, at 400, 401; see also
Alexander Hamilton, The Continentalist No. III, N.Y.
PACKET & AM. ADVERTISER, Aug. 9,
1781, reprinted in 2 T
HE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note 34, at 660, 665;
Alexander Hamilton, The Continentalist No. V, N.Y.
PACKET & AM. ADVERTISER, Apr. 18,
1782, reprinted in 3 T
HE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note 34, at 75, 75–76;
Alexander Hamilton, The Continentalist No. VI, N.Y.
PACKET & AM. ADVERTISER, July 4,
1782, reprinted in 3
THE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note 34, at 99, 99–104
[hereinafter Hamilton, The Continentalist No. VI]. See generally Alexander Hamilton, The
Continentalist No. IV, N.Y.
PACKET & AM. ADVERTISER, Aug. 30, 1781, reprinted in 2 THE
PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note 34, at 669.
63. Letter from Alexander Hamilton to James Duane, supra note 62, at 404.
64. Id. at 402–06; see also Hamilton, supra note 61, at 649–52; Hamilton, The
Continentalist No. VI, supra note 62, at 105–06.
65. Letter from Alexander Hamilton to James Duane, supra note 62, at 401.
66. Id.; see also A
LEXANDER HAMILTON, A LETTER FROM PHOCION TO THE CONSIDERATE
CITIZENS OF NEW YORK ON THE POLITICS OF THE DAY (New York, Samuel Loudon 1784),
reprinted in 3
THE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note 34, at 483, 489–92.
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1795
beginning, with many (if not, perhaps, all) inherent national powers.
67
While, for political reasons, it was surely necessary to call a general
convention to redraw the formal outlines of national power, Hamilton, the
prodigiously talented New Yorker, claimed that it would be every bit as
legitimate for Congress to merely “resum[e] and exercis[e] the discretionary
powers . . . originally vested in them.”
68
As the decade unfolded, Hamilton broadened his argument. Primarily in
the context of defending former loyalists against what he took to be punitive
postwar laws, he emphasized the obligations that the law of nations had
placed on the United States.
69
Because, in his judgment, New York’s anti-
loyalist legislation violated the peace treaty that Congress had negotiated
with Britain and other European nations, the legislation violated the law of
nations.
70
In making these arguments, Hamilton was further stressing the
essential ways in which the United States had behaved as a sovereign nation
and assumed the responsibilities of one. In claiming that the separate states
were obligated to comply with the law of nations as well as the nation’s treaty
obligations, Hamilton underscored the legal existence of the nation.
71
Hamilton offered a conspicuous account of incipient nationhood and the
exercise of its concomitant power. But even if he pointed to the nation’s
legal existence, he had not quite offered an account of that nation’s origins
or political foundations. That task would fall to other nationalist-minded
champions of constitutional reform.
James Wilson, the Pennsylvania lawyer and adroit constitutional thinker,
helped fill in the gaps that Hamilton had left—all while offering the most
penetrating account of American nationhood and power advanced in the
years prior to the Constitutional Convention.
72
Like Hamilton, Wilson had
served in Congress and helped lead the nationalist charge from its earliest
days.
73
Also like Hamilton, he simultaneously favored constitutional change
on the ground that the Confederation government was much too weak, while
defending that same government’s unrecognized inherent powers.
74
Unlike
Hamilton, however, he tethered a recognition of nationhood and inherent
67. Letter from Alexander Hamilton to James Duane, supra note 62, at 401–02.
68. Id. at 407.
69. Daniel J. Hulsebosch, A Discrete and Cosmopolitan Minority: The Loyalists, the
Atlantic World, and the Origins of Judicial Review, 81 C
HI.-KENT L. REV. 825, 844–46 (2006)
(describing Hamilton’s legal work defending a loyalist in Rutgers v. Waddington). For a
discussion of the broader phenomenon of state legislatures passing punitive laws against
former loyalists, see generally id.
70. See 1 T
HE LAW PRACTICE OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON: DOCUMENTS AND COMMENTARY
356 (Julius Goebel Jr. ed., 1964) (excerpting notes Hamilton made to prepare for his client’s
defense in Rutgers v. Waddington).
71. See Hulsebosch, supra note 69, at 844–46. On nationalists’ commitment to the law
of nations at this time, see generally Golove & Hulsebosch, supra note 10.
72. On Wilson’s constitutionalism, see generally Robert Green McCloskey, Introduction
to 1 J
AMES WILSON, THE WORKS OF JAMES WILSON 1 (Robert Green McCloskey ed., 1967).
73. On the alliance nationalists forged beginning in the early 1780s, see J
ACK N. RAKOVE,
THE BEGINNINGS OF NATIONAL POLITICS: AN INTERPRETIVE HISTORY OF THE CONTINENTAL
CONGRESS 183–84, 293–94, 307, 319–26 (1979).
74. See Gienapp, National Power and the Presidency, supra note 15, at 133–34, 144–45.
1796 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
national power to an account of the nation’s underlying social compact,
explaining more precisely why an American nation existed and how that fact
impacted the resulting delegation of authority to that nation’s government.
75
Wilson did so in defense of the national government’s authority under the
Articles of Confederation to establish the nation’s first national bank: the
Bank of North America.
76
The Articles had both failed to enumerate the
relevant power and also made clear that the state governments retained all
powers “not . . . expressly delegated.”
77
Nevertheless, Wilson explained, the
inquiry needed to begin not with the Articles but rather with the Declaration
of Independence—which, he contended, had established not thirteen
autonomous states but a single nation, and with it, a national people.
78
Consequently, the government presiding over that nation was the creation,
not of the people of the states but of the sovereign people of the United States.
This meant that the national government derived its powers from two
separate sources: some were expressly delegated by the states through the
Articles, but others “result[ed] from the union of the whole.”
79
“The United
States,” Wilson contended, “have general rights, general powers, and
general obligations, not derived from any particular States, nor from all the
particular States . . . but resulting from the union of the whole.”
80
Any power
that was general in character—that which the separate states could not
competently exercise on their own—was delegated independent of the
states.
81
Upon separating from Great Britain, those powers were assigned to
the Union as a whole and the subsequent “confederation,” Wilson stressed,
did not “weaken or abridge the powers and rights, to which the United States
were previously entitled.”
82
These broad powers did not amount to national
plenary power—many significant powers were reserved to the states.
83
But
there was considerable space between a national government vested with
plenary authority and one that was limited to formally delegated powers.
84
It
was easy to reject the latter without embracing the former, and Wilson
assumed, drawing on social contract theory, that a credible account of
national power rested somewhere between those poles.
85
Wilson had established, to his satisfaction, a basis for a national social
compact. Independence had created a national people, not merely a
collection of distinct peoples in distinct states. The Declaration of
Independence itself—by speaking on behalf of a plural noun, these U
NITED
75. See Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given, supra note 15, at 201–02.
76. See generally W
ILSON, supra note 59.
77. A
RTICLES OF CONFEDERATION of 1781, art. II.
78. W
ILSON, supra note 59, at 10.
79. Id.
80. Id.
81. Id.
82. Id.
83. See id. at 9.
84. See id. at 10.
85. Id. at 9–11.
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1797
colonies”—recognized that broader collective.
86
Because a national people
and a national polity preceded the Articles of Confederation, the
Confederation government derived its authority every bit as much from the
nation that it governed as it did from the states that delegated particular
powers to it.
87
“To many purposes,” Wilson wrote, “the United States are to
be considered as one undivided, independent nation; and as possessed of all
the rights, and powers, and properties, by the law of nations incident to
such.”
88
The nature of the Union dictated the powers of government, so for
Wilson, and nationalists to follow,
89
it made all the difference in the world
that the nation had come first.
III.
CONSTITUTING A NATION: THE CONSTITUTIONAL CONVENTION
This form of nationalist thinking, which assumed that a national social
contract had been forged through the act of independence, emerged swiftly
and potently at the Constitutional Convention. In an early debate with Luther
Martin over the nature of the Union, Wilson brandished the Declaration
90
and quoted from it at length (something that was highly unusual for the
time),
91
confident that it confirmed that “the United Colonies were
originally “independent, not Individually but Unitedly.”
92
Independence had
brought a national people into being and with it a national social compact.
The task in Philadelphia was to devise a new constitution for that particular
compact. Hamilton immediately “assented to the doctrine of Mr. Wilson,”
denying (no doubt based on his own earlier reflections on the subject) “the
doctrine that the States were thrown into a State of nature” through
independence.
93
Wilson even insisted that “[i]n the beginning . . . congress
themselves were as one state”—a single national body presiding over a
86. Id. at 10 (alteration in original) (quoting THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 5
(U.S. 1776)).
87. See supra notes 78–86 and accompanying text.
88. W
ILSON, supra note 59, at 10.
89. See infra Part III.
90. Danielle Allen and Emily Sneff have persuasively argued that Wilson likely
commissioned a previously unknown copy of the Declaration of Independence—the “Sussex
Declaration”—for his own personal use. See Danielle Allen & Emily Sneff, Golden Letters:
James Wilson, the Declaration of Independence, and the Sussex Declaration, 17 G
EO. J.L. &
PUB. POLY 193, 209–16 (2019). Furthermore, Wilson possibly read from this version at the
Convention. See id. at 218–23. Unlike the official Declaration, the Sussex Declaration
emphasized collective national unity by placing the names of the signatories together rather
than grouping them by the delegates’ states of origin. See id. at 214–16.
91. Few Americans paid much attention to the Declaration at this time, as the document
had been long forgotten. See P
AULINE MAIER, AMERICAN SCRIPTURE: MAKING THE
DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 154–70 (1997). Only later did it become a revered text. See
id. at 170–89; see also Bernadette Meyler, Between the States and the Signers: The Politics
of the Declaration of Independence Before the Civil War, 89 S.
CAL. L. REV. 541, 553–71
(2016) (describing how, in the early decades of the nineteenth century, the Declaration became
a contested political symbol that was used to justify rival accounts of union).
92. 1 T
HE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 324 (Max Farrand ed.,
1911) [hereinafter FARRANDS RECORDS] (June 19, 1787) (statement of James Wilson).
93. Id. at 324 (June 19, 1787) (statement of Alexander Hamilton).
1798 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
nation.
94
At this time, he suggested (rather implausibly but in order to stress
his own point about the Declaration) “dissentions or state interests were not
known.”
95
Rufus King, a leading nationalist from Massachusetts, agreed but took the
point in a different direction. Because they did not precede the nation,
“[n]one of the states are now sovereign or independent,” he declared.
96
They
were, in fact, “subordinate corporations or Societies.”
97
If they formed a
confederacy in some respects,” importantly, “they formed a Nation in
others.”
98
It was not out of necessity or the needs of confederation that so
“[m]any . . . essential rights are vested in congress,” King explained.
99
There
was a crucial, underlying reason why “[n]one of the states, individually or
collectively, but in congress, have the rights of peace or war.”
100
That was
because, as he tellingly put it, “[t]his is a union of the men of those states.”
101
Indeed, a “Union of the States is a union of the men composing them, from
whence a national character results to the whole.”
102
The Union was a
compact of a national people, of individuals who lived in separate states but,
from the standpoint of sovereignty, were not of the separate states. “To
certain points,” King therefore proclaimed, “we are now a united people.”
103
“Consolidation,” he observed, “is already established.”
104
As Hamilton had
argued several years earlier, it was already a brute fact.
105
This was why
King considered “the proposed Government as substantially and formally, a
General and National Government over the people of America”—precisely
because it was over the people of America, rather than the people of the
several states.
106
These arguments regarding the nature of the polity
provided a crucial foundation from which so many other delegates claimed
throughout the Convention that, as Hamilton put it, the “national government
ought . . . to have full sovereignty.”
107
94. Id. at 170 (June 8, 1787) (statement of James Wilson).
95. Id. Though, however implausible it might have been, it is worth stressing how
ambiguous the legal status of the states was during these early years of the Union. See Mark
A. Graber, State Constitutions as National Constitutions, 69 A
RK. L. REV. 371, 373–78, 421–
23 (2016) (investigating “early state constitutions, state declarations of independence, and
state instructions to delegates to the Continental Congress” for evidence of how state leaders
conceived of the states’ legal condition).
96. 1 F
ARRANDS RECORDS, supra note 92, at 328 (June 19, 1787) (statement of Rufus
King).
97. Id. at 331.
98. Id. at 324.
99. Id. at 328.
100. Id.
101. Id.
102. Id. at 323.
103. Id. at 328.
104. Id.
105. See Hamilton, supra note 61, at 649; Letter from Alexander Hamilton to James Duane,
supra note 62, at 401, 407.
106. 2 F
ARRANDS RECORDS, supra note 92, at 6 (July 14, 1787) (statement of Rufus King).
107. 1 id. at 328 (June 19, 1787) (statement of Alexander Hamilton); see also id. at 305
(June 18, 1787) (outline of statement of Alexander Hamilton).
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1799
The nationalist understanding of the polity also shaped the drafting of the
Constitution in profound ways. In particular, it no doubt shaded how many
delegates understood the enumeration of legislative powers that were
eventually written into Article I. The mere fact of the enumeration did not
mean, to their eyes, that national power was limited to it. As John Mikhail
has shown, with his theory of delegated national authority surely in mind,
Wilson dramatically revised what became the Necessary and Proper Clause
while serving on the Committee of Detail (the committee charged with
compiling a working draft of the Constitution roughly halfway through the
Convention).
108
The national legislature would enjoy the power to make all
necessary and proper laws, not only to carry out its “foregoing powers” (those
enumerated in what would become Article I, Section 8) but also “all other
Powers” that had been vested “in the Government of the United States.”
109
This clause confirmed that there were “other Powers,” independent of
anything enumerated, that were delegated to the national government as a
whole, based on the character of the preexisting union. These revisions
provided a textual reminder of what nationalists already assumed to be the
case: that certain national powers resulted from the formation of the
American Union itself.
110
These powers were not “vested” via text but
through an entirely different mechanism. And thus, the phrase “this
Constitution,” found in the “necessary and proper” clause and elsewhere
throughout the document, described not merely the textual content being
written in Philadelphia but also, necessarily, the underlying constitution of
the polity on which that text would fundamentally be based. Those powers
“vested” by “this Constitution,” therefore, could not be identified solely
based on the expressed text found in the written Constitution, because the
content of “this Constitution” was as much a function of the kind of sovereign
people who had established it as it was the discrete textual provisions written
into it.
108. Mikhail, The Necessary and Proper Clauses, supra note 15, at 1096–106. For the
definitive study of the Committee of Detail, see William Ewald, The Committee of Detail, 28
C
ONST. COMMENT. 197 (2012). On Wilson’s role on the committee, see id. at 213–14, 242–
46, 276–83. For the committee’s appointment, see 2 F
ARRANDS RECORDS, supra note 92, at
87, 95–98, 106. For the committee’s work, see id. at 129–74.
109. U.S.
CONST. art. I, § 8; Mikhail, The Necessary and Proper Clauses, supra note 15, at
1099–101, 1121–28.
110. See, e.g., W
ILSON, supra note 59, at 10–11; supra notes 92–107 and accompanying
text. Nationalists, therefore, presumably believed that the final enumeration of legislative
powers found in the Constitution incorporated, rather than eliminated, the principle advanced
in Resolution VI of the Virginia Plan (the initial draft for a new constitution presented at the
Convention). Resolution VI called to vest the national legislature with the authority “to
legislate in all cases to which the separate states are incompetent” or “in which the harmony
of the United States may be interrupted.” See 1 F
ARRANDS RECORDS, supra note 92, at 21
(May 29, 1787) (Virginia Plan). The Committee of Detail replaced Resolution VI with an
enumeration of legislative powers, but social contract theory enabled nationalists to explain
why Resolution VI endured—why, thanks to the nature of union, the national government
already claimed the authority to address genuinely national ends. See Gienapp, National
Power and the Presidency, supra note 15, at 145–46.
1800 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
Wilson’s Committee of Detail work was soon fortified by his nationalist
ally, Gouverneur Morris, on the Committee of Style—which was assigned
the task of producing a final draft of the Constitution.
111
Morris, quite
possibly with Wilson’s assistance,
112
dramatically reworked the
Constitution’s Preamble (which Wilson had initially drafted on the
Committee of Detail).
113
Of enormous importance for the nationalist cause,
the final version unambiguously established “We the People of the United
States” as the Constitution’s founding agent.
114
Especially when combined
with what punctuated the document—rules for ratification that empowered
the people themselves, acting through special ratifying conventions, rather
than the state legislatures, to consider the new Constitution
115
—these
opening words did away with the lingering residue of the Articles. Even
under the Articles, the states could only delegate and retain those powers they
could competently exercise;
116
but now, by so dramatically undermining the
states’ claims to sovereign authority, the Constitution further underscored the
primacy of the Union. Or so nationalists believed.
117
In addition, and as
important, the final Preamble specified six specific purposes for which the
new national government would be established—including the need to
“promote the General Welfare”
118
—which could be read as the referent of
the “all other powers” so conspicuously referenced in the revised “necessary
and proper” clause: a set of national ends that a national people licensed its
national government to pursue.
119
The Preamble was proof positive of the importance of social contract
theory to the nationalist view. It served as the clearest evidence imaginable
of how so many Federalists understood the nature of the American social
compact and thus, would have read the final Constitution.
120
Like the “all
other powers” clause, the Preamble did not vest any power in the new
government but rather reinforced what was already believed to be vested,
121
111. See 2 FARRANDS RECORDS, supra note 92, at 547, 553 (documenting the appointment
of a committee “to revise the style of and arrange the articles agreed to” and listing Gouverneur
Morris as a committee member); id. at 565–80 (documenting the committee’s final work).
112. Even though Wilson was not formally appointed to the Committee of Style, he might
have unofficially helped with the final drafting. Based on a visit with Convention delegate
Abraham Baldwin of Georgia, Ezra Stiles of Connecticut recorded in his diary that Baldwin
had claimed “Messrs Morris & Wilson had the chief hand in the last Arrangt & Composition”
of the Constitution. See Ezra Stiles, Diary (Dec. 21, 1787), reprinted in 3 F
ARRANDS
RECORDS, supra note 97, at 168, 170.
113. William Michael Treanor, The Case of the Dishonest Scrivener: Gouverneur Morris
and the Creation of the Federalist Constitution, 119 M
ICH. L. REV. (forthcoming 2021)
(manuscript at 78–87), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3383183 [https://
perma.cc/UHT8-LZGV].
114. U.S.
CONST. pmbl.
115. Id. art. VII.
116. See W
ILSON, supra note 59, at 10.
117. See Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given, supra note 15, at 198–99.
118. U.S.
CONST. pmbl.
119. Mikhail, The Constitution and the Philosophy of Language, supra note 15, at 1097–
103.
120. See supra notes 113–19 and accompanying text.
121. See supra notes 109–10 and accompanying text.
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1801
serving as both proof of a particular understanding of the federal Union and
reminder of what necessarily followed from that fact. As under the Articles,
the proposed national government lacked plenary authority. But thanks to
the polity set to establish it, the government would enjoy vastly more
authority than the sum of enumerated powers expressed in the written
Constitution. As far as nationalists were concerned, the national government
would have all of the power entitled to a government established by a national
people and its nation—no more, no less.
IV.
WE THE PEOPLE VS. WE THE STATES: RATIFICATION
During ratification, several nationalists drew out these readings, appealing
to social contract theory to explicate and defend the proposed Constitution.
James Wilson, fresh off his command performance in Philadelphia, was
especially eager to ground understanding of the new system of government
in a debate over the nature of the polity.
122
What was the Constitution and
who had authorized it? Critics were confused on both counts, Wilson
contended, for contrary to what they maintained, “[t]his . . . is not a
government founded upon compact.”
123
That was because “[t]here can be
no compact unless there are more parties than one,”
124
and the Constitution
recognized but one party: “W
E, THE PEOPLE OF THE UNITED STATES.”
125
If
one studied the Preamble and the document as a whole, “the system itself
tells you what it is,” Wilson stressed.
126
It was neither a treaty nor a peace
pact; rather, “it is an ordinance and establishment of the people”—a national
people.
127
Of course, many founding-era Americans sharply disagreed with the
nationalists’ aims, but beginning with the ratification debates, to a striking
degree, disputes over the Constitution were defined on the nationalists’
terms.
128
Indeed, it was precisely because nationalists such as Wilson,
Morris, King, and Hamilton were right—if not about how much national
power was preferable, then about the relationship between the constitution of
the polity and the constitution of its government—that opponents found the
proposed Constitution so threatening.
129
The Preamble immediately caught anti-Federalists’ attention. I confess,”
Samuel Adams uneasily reported, “as I enter the Building I stumble at the
Threshold. I meet with a National Government, instead of a f[e]deral Union
122. See infra notes 123–27 and accompanying text.
123. 2 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION:
PENNSYLVANIA 550, 552, 555 (Merrill Jensen ed., 1976) (Dec. 11, 1787) (statement of James
Wilson).
124. Id. at 555.
125. 2 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION:
PENNSYLVANIA, supra note 123, at 465, 493–94 (Dec. 4, 1787) (statement of James Wilson).
126. Id. at 556 (Dec. 11, 1787) (statement of James Wilson).
127. Id. at 555–56.
128. Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given, supra note 15, at 198–201, 204–05.
129. Id. at 204–05.
1802 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
of Sovereign States.”
130
At its “very commencement,” observed Cincinnatus
in direct response to Wilson, the Constitution “prescribe[s] this remarkable
declaration—We the People of the United States.”
131
Patrick Henry echoed
this sentiment most famously, asking why the Constitution began: “We, the
People, instead of We, the States?”
132
While Henry’s quip is best known, it
was hardly the only one.
The Preamble proved so threatening because anti-Federalists perfectly
understood, much as Federalists did, that it revealed something substantive
about the kind of union the United States would be under the Constitution.
The proposed Constitution presupposed a certain kind of federal polity, one
that revealed it to be “a compact between individuals entering into society,”
William Findley observed, “and not between separate states enjoying
independent power and delegating a portion of that power for their common
benefit.”
133
Indeed, Robert Whitehill claimed in the Pennsylvania ratifying
convention, the Preamble showed “the principle of confederation excluded,
and a new unwieldy system of consolidated empire . . . set up upon [it].”
134
Thanks to what it said about the underlying polity, anti-Federalists assumed,
the Constitution entitled the national government to more power than was
expressly enumerated. “The inference is natural,” Brutus complained,
135
based on “the great end of the constitution . . . to be collected from the
preamble,”
136
that “the [national] legislature will have an authority to make
all laws which they shall judge necessary for the common safety, and to
promote the general welfare.”
137
These implications were only reinforced,
an anti-Federalist author writing under the pseudonym “An Old Whig”
138
130. Letter from Samuel Adams to Richard Henry Lee (Dec. 3, 1787), in 4 THE
DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: MASSACHUSETTS 349,
349 (John P. Kaminski et al. eds., 1997).
131. Cincinnatus V: To James Wilson, Esquire,
N.Y.J., Nov. 29, 1787, reprinted in 14 THE
DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE
CONSTITUTION, supra note 40, at 303, 307.
132. 9 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: VIRGINIA
915, 930 (John P. Kaminski et al. eds., 1990) (June 4, 1788) (statement of Patrick Henry).
133. 2 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION:
PENNSYLVANIA, supra note 123, at 444, 447–48 (Dec. 1, 1787) (statement of William Findley);
see also Luther Martin, Genuine Information IV, B
ALT. MD. GAZETTE, Jan. 8, 1788, reprinted
in 15 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION:
COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION, supra note 40, at 296, 297 (“It is in its very
introduction declared to be a compact between the people of the United States as
individuals . . . .”).
134. 2 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION:
PENNSYLVANIA, supra note 123, at 382, 393 (Nov. 28, 1787) (statement of Robert Whitehill).
135. Brutus V,
N.Y.J., Dec. 13, 1787, reprinted in 14 THE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE
RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION, supra note 40,
at 422, 423.
136. Brutus XII, N.Y.J., Feb. 7, 1788, reprinted in 16 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE
RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION, supra note 40,
at 72, 74.
137. Brutus V,
supra note 135, at 423.
138. Some believe that “An Old Whig” was George Bryan, either writing alone or as part
of a wider group of writers. See 13 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE
CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION, supra note 40, at 376.
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1803
believed, by the inclusion of a clause “for carrying into execution A
LL OTHER
POWERS,” which indicated that “other powers may be assumed hereafter as
contained by implication in this constitution.”
139
Nationalists were not alone
in their reading of the Necessary and Proper Clause, in particular Wilson’s
strategic changes to it.
Those Federalists who were less committed to expansive national power,
such as James Madison, worked to reassure anti-Federalists that the proposed
Constitution delegated powers that were, in fact, “few and defined.”
140
Though, importantly, Madison’s disagreement with the nationalists did not
stop there. Despite supporting the Constitution, he resisted the nationalist
account of union. While it might have seemed, Madison argued, “that the
Constitution is to be founded on the assent and ratification of the people of
America,” on closer examination, that “assent and ratification is to be given
by the people, not as individuals composing one entire nation; but as
composing the distinct and independent States to which they respectively
belong.”
141
Therefore, the “act . . . establishing the Constitution,” he
concluded, will not be a national but a federal act.”
142
Madison thus
believed that national powers under the Constitution would be few and
defined,” in part, because a nonnational people were set to establish its
legitimacy.
143
Nationalists such as Wilson, who insisted, in contrast to Madison, that the
Constitution would be “ordained and established by the people
themselves”
144
because “[t]here can be no compact unless there are more
parties than one,”
145
nonetheless, on account of the rhetorical and political
needs of the moment, offered their own reassurances to anti-Federalists.
Being the skilled lawyer that he was, however, Wilson made sure to leave
room for his own genuine understandings of national power and union. For
instance, “where the powers are particularly enumerated,” he pledged “the
implied result is, that nothing more is intended to be given, than what is so
139. An Old Whig II, PHILA. INDEP. GAZETTEER, Oct. 17, 1787, reprinted in 13 THE
DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE
CONSTITUTION, supra note 40, at 399, 402–03.
140. T
HE FEDERALIST NO. 45 (James Madison), reprinted in 15 THE DOCUMENTARY
HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION,
supra note 40, at 476, 479; see also 27 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF
THE
CONSTITUTION: SOUTH CAROLINA 90, 97 (John P. Kaminski et al. eds., 2016) (Jan. 16,
1788) (statement of Charles Pinckney) (“The distinction which has often been taken between
the nature of a federal and state government appeared to be conclusive—that in the former no
powers could be executed or assumed but such as were expressly delegated, and in the latter
the indefinite power was given to the government, except upon points that were by express
compact reserved to the people.”).
141. T
HE FEDERALIST NO. 39 (James Madison), reprinted in 15 THE DOCUMENTARY
HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION: COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION,
supra note 40, at 380, 383.
142. Id.
143. T
HE FEDERALIST NO. 45 (James Madison), supra note 140, at 479.
144. 2 T
HE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION:
PENNSYLVANIA, supra note 123, at 550, 556 (Dec. 11, 1787) (statement of James Wilson).
145. Id. at 555.
1804 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
enumerated, unless,” he made sure to add, it results from the nature of the
government itself.”
146
The federal government would be able to exercise
only those powers delegated to it, but that, of course, raised the question of
how power was delegated under a constitution like the one proposed in the
first place. Here, Wilson reminded careful listeners: “I consider the people
of the United States, as forming one great community,” while “the people of
the different states” formed communities “on a lesser scale.”
147
From this
great division of the people into distinct communities,” he went on, different
allotments of power were given to the governments, according to the nature,
number, and magnitude of their objects.”
148
Those objects were a function
of the polity that constituted the government. The sum of delegated authority
was limited to what happened to be enumerated if—and only ifthe
underlying polity happened to be a collection of sovereign states rather than
a far-flung sovereign people. If it was the latter—as nationalists insisted it
was—then the sum of delegated power was greater than if it was not.
No matter how many Federalists hinted otherwise to help ensure
ratification, therefore, few skeptics were pacified by these assurances
because the Federalists’ foundational assumption resonated. Most assumed
that there was indeed an inescapable relationship between the constitutional
text and the underlying polity, one that could not be ignored.
V.
DEBATING NATIONAL POWER THROUGH THE NATURE OF THE POLITY
After ratification, these fault lines continued to shape constitutional debate
in profound ways. To an extent often not appreciated, defenders of national
power instinctively appealed to the kinds of nationalist social contract
arguments that had emerged in the 1780s and to powerful effect.
They did so in a range of important debates, though perhaps nowhere quite
as significantly as during the debate over Alexander Hamilton’s proposed
national bank.
149
In the House of Representatives, bank defenders appealed
to the nature of the polity and government with as much frequency as they
parsed the Constitution’s textual commands. They claimed, as Wilson and
King had earlier, that the national government’s power was shaped by the
character of the underlying federal union: “by the very nature of
government,” contended Fisher Ames, the quick-witted representative from
Massachusetts, “the legislature had an implied power of using every mean
not positively prohibited by the constitution, to execute the ends for which
that government was instituted.”
150
The Preamble, he continued, “vested
146. 2 THE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION:
PENNSYLVANIA, supra note 123, at 465, 470 (emphasis added) (Dec. 4, 1787) (statement of
James Wilson).
147. Id. at 472.
148. Id.
149. Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given, supra note 15, at 205–11. On the
bank debate as a whole, see J
ONATHAN GIENAPP, THE SECOND CREATION: FIXING THE
AMERICAN CONSTITUTION IN THE FOUNDING ERA 202–47 (2018).
150. Philadelphia, Feb. 9., GEN. ADVERTISER (Phila.), Feb. 9, 1791, reprinted in 14
D
OCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST FEDERAL CONGRESS OF THE UNITED STATES OF
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1805
Congress with the authority over all objects of national concern or of a
general nature.”
151
Numerous bank defenders echoed Ames. “The principles of the
government and ends of the constitution,” John Laurance declared, “were
expressed in the preamble.”
152
Among those principles was the fact of a
national people and polity. As John Vining of Delaware explained, by virtue
of the Declaration of Independence, the United States “derive[d] all the
powers appertaining to a nation,” which included the specific power under
consideration”—the right to charter a national bank.
153
When it came time for Hamilton to offer his own opinion on the
constitutionality of the proposed bank, he too relied on social contract
principles to justify a more expansive set of powers for the national
government, though his appeal to these precepts was subtler.
154
He did not
underscore the Preamble, nor did he speak explicitly about a national people
having formed a national polity.
155
But he did allude to the formation of
political society to justify a broad interpretation of the Constitution’s powers.
“[A]ll government is a delegation of power,” he wrote, and “how much is
delegated in each case” turned on “fair reasoning & construction upon the
particular provisions of the constitution—taking as guides the general
principles & general ends of government.”
156
Interpretation needed to be
guided by a fair assessment of the general principles and ends of government,
something to be derived from the formation of the underlying social
compact.
157
With these ends of government in mind, it was fair to assume
that “the powers contained in a constitution of government . . . ought to be
construed liberally, in advancement of the public good.”
158
Because the
American people had entered into a common political society—that is,
because they had formed a national social compact—the government
established for that society was necessarily empowered to promote the
general welfare.
159
As long as a liberal exercise of power was “not contrary
AMERICA 385, 386 (Charlene Bangs Bickford et al. eds., 1995) (statement of Fisher Ames,
Feb. 3, 1791).
151. Philadelphia, Feb. 10., G
EN. ADVERTISER (Phila.), Feb. 10, 1791, reprinted in 14
D
OCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST FEDERAL CONGRESS OF THE UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA, supra note 150, at 387, 389 (statement of Fisher Ames, Feb. 3, 1791).
152. Philadelphia, Feb. 15., G
EN. ADVERTISER (Phila.), Feb. 15, 1791, reprinted in 14
D
OCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST FEDERAL CONGRESS OF THE UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA, supra note 150, at 412, 413 (statement of John Laurance, Feb. 4, 1791).
153. Congress. House of Representatives. Tuesday, Feb. 8., G
AZETTE OF THE U.S. (Phila.),
Apr. 16, 1791, reprinted in 14 D
OCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST FEDERAL CONGRESS OF
THE
UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, supra note 150, at 471, 472 (statement of John Vining, Feb.
8, 1791).
154. For a related discussion, see Campbell, supra note 19, at 101–03.
155. Gienapp, The Myth of the Constitutional Given, supra note 15, at 208–09.
156. Alexander Hamilton, Final Version of an Opinion on the Constitutionality of an Act
to Establish a Bank (1791), reprinted in 8 T
HE PAPERS OF ALEXANDER HAMILTON, supra note
34, at 97, 100 (emphasis added).
157. See id.
158. Id. at 105.
159. See id.
1806 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
to the essential ends of political society,” then that government was justified
to pursue the general purposes for which that society had been established in
the first place.
160
To an important degree, then, Hamilton based his argument
on an account of the nation’s underlying compact.
Even more emphatically, the U.S. Supreme Court’s ruling in Chisholm v.
Georgia,
161
orchestrated by leading nationalists Justice James Wilson and
Chief Justice John Jay, firmly relied on social contract theory. The entire
question of whether states could be sued by residents of other states came
down, in their minds, to the nature of the United States itself—to what kind
of people and community had given life to the Constitution.
162
The
distribution of sovereignty in the Union tracked the nature of the Union and
turned on the kind of people that had brought it into being. The
Constitution’s text did not, and could not, stand alone. Its meaning was,
ultimately, a function of the kind of sovereign agent who had authorized it
and, in turn, the kind of union for which that sovereign agent spoke. Just as
in the eyes of leading Federalists it was impossible to determine whether the
national government enjoyed a power to charter a national bank without first
understanding the character of the Union,
163
so too was it impossible to sort
out state suability (and related issues of retained sovereignty) by simply
fixating on the Constitution’s expressed text. The issue in Chisholm turned
on a question that preceded the text: whether the United States was a nation
of genuine legal standing.
164
In determining the issue in question, Wilson dissected principles of general
jurisprudence, the laws and practices of the various states, and the law of the
Constitution.
165
But all of this detailed analysis was preceded by a more
basic consideration, one that ultimately shaped and, in many ways, drove the
remainder of the inquiry. “The question to be determined,” he stated at the
outset,
is, whether this State, so respectable, and whose claim soars so high, is
amenable to the jurisdiction of the Supreme Court of the United States?
This question, important in itself, will depend on others, more important
still; and, may, perhaps, be ultimately resolved into one, no less radical than
this—“do the people of the United States form a Nation?”
166
Here was the foundational question.
Answering it required probing the nature of sovereignty in the United
States and particularly the ways in which the American Revolution had
transformed it. In taking stock of Americans’ recent history, Wilson
remarked that all too often states and sovereigns had been conflated, a
mistake Americans had not made. “To the Constitution of the United States,”
160. Id. at 98.
161. 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 419 (1793).
162. Id. at 453, 470–71.
163. See supra notes 150–60 and accompanying text.
164. See supra note 162 and accompanying text.
165. Chisholm, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) at 453.
166. Id. (emphasis omitted).
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1807
he explained, “the term S
OVEREIGN, is totally unknown. There is but one
place where it could have been used with propriety . . . . [the] ‘S
OVEREIGN
people of the United States.”
167
Neither the nation-state nor the individual
states that comprised the American Union were sovereign.
168
Only the
people who had brought both kinds of states into being merited that exalted
designation.
169
(This, among many reasons, was, to Wilson’s mind, why
Blackstone’s theory of law, based on the command of a superior
governmental sovereign, was so deeply mistaken.)
170
If “the majesty of the
people,” rather than “the prerogative of Kings” or the “sovereignty of
[s]tates” (the conventional focus of political and legal writing), was the only
authority known in the wake of the Revolution, then the question boiled down
to: which kind of people?
171
For Wilson, the answer was clear: a national people. “[O]ur national scene
opens with the most magnificent object, which the nation could present,” he
averred, “‘[t]he P
EOPLE of the United States’ are the first personages
introduced.”
172
And, quoting the Preamble, he continued “[i]n order,
therefore, to form a more perfect union, to establish justice, to ensure
domestic tranquillity, to provide for common defence, and to secure the
blessings of liberty, those people, among whom were the people of Georgia,
ordained and established the present Constitution.”
173
Consequently, Wilson
concluded, taking “a combined and comprehensive view, the general texture
of the Constitution” confirmed that “the people of the United States intended
to form themselves into a nation for national purposes.”
174
Jay offered a comparable analysis. The matter of whether Georgia, or any
other state, enjoyed sovereign immunity turned on the Constitution’s legal
foundations. And on this score, what mattered above all was that “the people,
in their collective and national capacity, established the present
Constitution.”
175
Jay based this conclusion primarily on a historical account.
“The Revolution, or rather the Declaration of Independence,” he observed,
“found the people already united for general purposes.”
176
He continued:
From the crown of Great Britain, the sovereignty of their country passed to
the people of it; and it was then not an uncommon opinion, that the
unappropriated lands, which belonged to that crown, passed not to the
people of the Colony or States within whose limits they were situated, but
to the whole people . . . .
177
167. Id. at 454 (emphasis omitted).
168. See id.
169. See id.
170. Id. at 458.
171. Id. at 463 (emphasis omitted).
172. Id. (emphasis omitted).
173. Id. (emphasis omitted).
174. Id. at 465 (emphasis omitted).
175. Id. at 470.
176. Id.
177. Id. (emphasis omitted).
1808 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
Echoing Wilson’s argument in defense of the Bank of North America,
178
Jay
stressed that the act of declaring independence from Britain had established
a national people. This national people then gave voice to “their own proper
sovereignty” in “declar[ing] with becoming dignity, ‘We the people of the
United States, do ordain and establish this Constitution.’”
179
“Here we see,”
Jay noted, “the people acting as sovereigns of the whole country and in the
language of sovereignty, establishing a Constitution by which it was their
will that the State Governments should be bound, and to which the State
Constitutions should be made to conform.”
180
Everything came down to the
fact that a national people had brought the American legal order into being.
Of course, Chisholm caused consternation, and the Eleventh Amendment
eventually nullified its narrow holding.
181
But even if some people at the
time and many since have assumed that the Amendment established a broader
principle of state sovereign immunity, there is no reason to believe that
nationalists concluded that the amendment undermined the broader account
of national popular sovereignty on which the Court’s decision had been
based. To at least nationalist eyes, the Eleventh Amendment protected states
from retrospective liability on claims predating the Constitution.
182
But that
said nothing about claims incurred thereafter.
183
Nor, more importantly, did
it unsettle the fundamental principle announced in Chisholm, which remained
as undeniable as it had been since the Constitution took effect: that the
people of the United States, as a national people, had created a nation.
184
Wilson’s and Jay’s enquiries requires reinforced what so many nationalists
had to that point maintained: that the Preamble, far from the rhetorical
flourish to which it would later be reduced,
185
was the key to unlocking the
Constitution. It revealed what sort of thing the Constitution was, by
confirming what kind of people and polity it represented. It was evidence of
the Union’s underlying social contract. Beneath a national constitution could
be found a national people. It was, thus, utterly misguided—not to mention
legally mistaken—to view the Constitution as a treaty or anything
comparable. It was no such thing. It was a national constitution, and each
of those words mattered. As a constitution, it was predicated on the sovereign
will of a people. As a national constitution, it was predicated on the
sovereign will of a national people. Its character and authority could not be
divorced from the social compact that undergirded it.
178. See supra notes 76–85 and accompanying text.
179. Chisholm, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) at 471.
180. Id.
181. See U.S.
CONST. amend. XI; Pennhurst State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 465 U.S.
89, 97–98 (1984) (dicta) (stating that Chisholm “created such a shock of surprise that the
Eleventh Amendment was at once proposed and adopted” and that the Amendment “overruled
the particular result in Chisholm” (citation omitted)).
182. See James E. Pfander, History and State Suability: An “Explanatory” Account of the
Eleventh Amendment, 83 C
ORNELL L. REV. 1269, 1368–69 (1998).
183. Id. at 1343–52.
184. See supra notes 167–80 and accompanying text.
185. In 1905, the Supreme Court held that the Preamble was not a grant of power. See
Jacobson v. Massachusetts, 197 U.S. 11, 22 (1905).
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1809
During the Constitution’s earliest years, leading nationalists routinely
transformed debates over the limits of national power into ones over the
nature of the American polity.
186
Building on the ideas they had first
articulated in the 1780s, they imagined that national constitutional
interpretation was tightly entangled with issues of nationhood. Sorting out
the Constitution’s meaning required deciphering its underlying social
contract—grasping the compact and polity that preceded the constitution of
government. Whoever tried to limn the boundaries of national power based
solely on a textual analysis of the Constitution’s words betrayed ignorance
of what they were reading and the kind of legal content it contained—or so
Federalists insisted, time and again.
VI.
COMPACT THEORY: THE ULTIMATE CONCESSION
Strikingly, nationalists’ argument proved so resonant that their intellectual
opponents would come to tacitly agree with its underlying premise. Possibly
the strongest evidence of that argument’s resonance has been hiding in plain
sight. Only because nationalists were right about the implications of social
contract theory were anti-nationalists compelled to invent compact
theory
187
—the idea that the federal Union was a compact among sovereign
states rather than a national contract among the individuals of the United
States.
188
They conceded that the scope of the national government’s
authority was indeed determined by the nature of the preceding political
compact (the two-step logic of social contract theory), while denying
nationalists’ account of step one (the nature of the social compact found in
the United States). Rather than challenge nationalists’ logic, in other words,
anti-nationalists tried to refute the argument on its own terms. This implies
186. See supra Parts II–IV.
187. Because of how eighteenth-century constitutional and political authors wrote,
terminology can get tricky here. Social contract theory—which, to make things especially
confusing, was often itself called social compact theory—was the larger framework. As
discussed, this overarching theory presupposed a two-step process of political formation that
explained how human beings moved from the state of nature to living under government: step
one involved forming a social compact, while step two consisted of constituting a government
for that compact. See supra Part I. From within this framework, there were lots of different
ways to understand, as a matter of contingent fact, how one’s own political community had
been formed. Federalists, as we have seen, devised one alternative: people across the
American Union had formed a national social compact of individuals at the national level. See
supra Part II.
Compact theory, by contrast, presented a different alternative from within the framework of
social contract theory: people in the individual states had formed separate state social
compacts, followed by separate state governments, and only thereafter had they attended to
the Union as a whole. Compact theory, therefore, was neither a substitute for nor a competitor
to social contract (or social compact) theory. It was, instead, an application of social contract
theory—a particular account, based on the terms of social contract theory, of which kinds of
social compacts existed in the United States. See S
AUL CORNELL, THE OTHER FOUNDERS:
ANTI-FEDERALISM AND THE DISSENTING TRADITION IN AMERICA, 1788–1828, at 237–45
(1999); C
HRISTIAN G. FRITZ, AMERICAN SOVEREIGNS: THE PEOPLE AND AMERICAS
CONSTITUTIONAL TRADITION BEFORE THE CIVIL WAR 190–234 (2008).
188. C
ORNELL, supra note 187, at 237–45; FRITZ, supra note 187, at 190–234.
1810 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
something striking about founding-era constitutional assumptions and thus
the conceptual background against which the original Constitution was set.
Initially, skeptics of national power, most of whom rallied behind Thomas
Jefferson’s and James Madison’s opposition to the Washington
administration, and particularly Hamilton’s policies within it, tested different
arguments. Among other things, they pressed the Constitution’s text into
service, hopeful that they could confine the national government’s powers to
the express terms of the document. In the debate over the national bank, they
countered defenses of far-reaching national power by contending that, as
Madison famously argued, the Constitution’s “essential characteristic” was
that it established a government “of limited and enumerated powers.”
189
William Branch Giles of Virginia took this argument a step further, asserting
that “the peculiar nature of this government” lay in the fact that it was
“composed of mere chartered authorities.”
190
Accordingly, any “authority
not contained within that charter” was off-limits.
191
The soon-to-be Tenth
Amendment, which declared that the states retained all powers not delegated
to the federal government, Giles argued, underscored this essential point.
192
Throughout the 1790s, as the nation divided into discernible political
coalitions, these became common refrains among Jeffersonian
Republicans.
193
Yet, strikingly, champions of strict enumerated powers and the
Constitution’s written character recognized that limiting the scope of the
federal government’s power required challenging nationalists’ account of
federal union. Pointing to the enumeration of legislative powers or clamoring
about the Tenth Amendment only reinforced that the debate turned not on the
Constitution’s written content but on the operative meaning of “delegated.”
To claim that something about the Constitution’s writtenness settled the
matter already presupposed a robust understanding of how federal power
was, as an initial matter, delegated and, thus, what kind of polity had
constituted the federal government in the first place. That Republicans did
not ultimately rest their case on the inherent limitations of enumerated
powers but instead based it on a rival account of federal union, is conspicuous
acknowledgement that, to their minds, nationalists’ core premise was correct.
Republicans, consequently, began trumpeting compact theory. According
to the dominant version of this theory, there was no people of the United
States, no national social contract. There were peoples of the various states,
189. Congress. House of Representatives. Wednesday, Feb. 2., GAZETTE OF THE U.S.
(Phila.), Feb. 23, 1791, reprinted in 14 DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST FEDERAL
CONGRESS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 150, at 367, 371 (statement of James Madison,
Feb. 2, 1791).
190. Congress. House of Representatives. Saturday, Feb. 7., G
AZETTE OF THE U.S. (Phila.),
Apr. 6, 1791, reprinted in 14 D
OCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST FEDERAL CONGRESS OF
THE
UNITED STATES, supra note 150, at 466, 468 (statement of William Giles, Feb. 7, 1791).
191. Id.
192. Id.
193. On the origins of the nation’s first political parties, see generally E
LKINS &
MCKITRICK, supra note 10; GORDON S. WOOD, EMPIRE OF LIBERTY: A HISTORY OF THE EARLY
REPUBLIC, 1789–1815 (2009).
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1811
each of whom had created separate polities through state-level social
contracts.
194
These states had then compacted together to form a union, and
this was why federal power was inherently limited. Republicans, in other
words, accepted the premise, if not the conclusion, of nationalists’ argument.
At the Constitutional Convention, Gouverneur Morris had “explained the
distinction between a federal and national, supreme, Govt.; the former being
a mere compact . . . the latter having a compleat and compulsive
operation.”
195
Because, he went on, “in all communities there must be one
supreme power,” the question of delegated authority thus turned on whether
or not the United States formed one single political community.
196
Defeating
nationalists’ sweeping claims that the federal government could broadly
interpret the Constitution to promote the national public good meant cutting
them at their roots. It required demonstrating that the Union was not a single
political community but, in fact, several. It meant taking Morris’s logic and
distinctions seriously and, based on them, reaching an alternative conclusion.
When defending compact theory in 1798 in the Kentucky Resolutions,
Thomas Jefferson did just this. His arguments could not have been more
revealing. The Constitution, he asserted, was a “compact under the style and
title of a Constitution for the United States.”
197
This phrasing is worth a
careful look. No matter the Constitution’s own style and form, which
otherwise seemed to present it as a constitution (signaled nowhere more
clearly than in the Preamble), it was actually something else entirely: a
compact.
198
This foundational statement colored everything that followed,
including especially what came next. The resolutions claimed that the
“several states composing the United States of America . . . [had] constituted
a General Government for special purposes, delegat[ing] to that Government
certain definite powers” while “reserving . . . the residuary mass” to
themselves, meaning any assumption on the part of the national government
of “undelegated powers” was, accordingly, “void, and of no force.”
199
These
claims about enumeration and the express delegation and reservation of
powers rested on the initial premise that there was no federal polity and that
the “style and form” of the Constitution was misleading.
200
These arguments became doctrinaire among Republicans. Virginian John
Taylor claimed that “the people in state conventions,” in their capacity as the
peoples of the individual states, were “incontrovertibly the contracting
parties” of the Constitution.
201
In The Report of 1800, written in defense of
194. See FRITZ, supra note 187, at 194–96, 198–99.
195. 1 F
ARRANDS RECORDS, supra note 92, at 34 (May 30, 1787) (statement of Gouverneur
Morris).
196. Id.
197. Thomas Jefferson, Resolutions Adopted by the Kentucky General Assembly (Nov.
10, 1798), reprinted in 30 T
HE PAPERS OF THOMAS JEFFERSON 550, 550 (Barbara B. Oberg et
al. eds., 2003).
198. See id.
199. See id.
200. See id.
201. Letter from John Taylor to Thomas Jefferson (June 25, 1798), in 30 T
HE PAPERS OF
THOMAS JEFFERSON, supra note 197, at 430, 434.
1812 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 89
the Virginia and Kentucky Resolutions, Madison similarly regarded “the
people composing” the “political societies” of the various states as having
acted “in their highest sovereign capacity” when they ratified the
Constitution.
202
Meanwhile, a few years later, in 1803, the leading legal
theorist of the Republican movement, St. George Tucker,
203
systematically
defended this point in an extensive essay appending his annotated (and
Americanized) edition of Blackstone’s Commentaries.
204
The federal
government’s powers were confined to those written, Tucker argued, because
the Constitution was a compact among sovereign states; there was no national
polity, just a national government brought into being by separate peoples in
separate states.
205
There was no escaping, it seemed, the recognition that
constitutional powers derived, in some significant sense, from the nature of
the American Union. Republicans certainly seemed content to argue on the
terms that Federalists had so spiritedly defended and leveraged to such effect.
Why, we ought to ask, did Republicans feel a need to construct compact
theory? Why did they not simply fall back on strict construction or point to
the Constitution’s enumerated powers or putative writtenness? Because, it
would seem, they believed that Federalists were right: if, as a point of fact,
there was a national polity, then the national government would indeed have
claim to more power than if there was not. Compact theory was designed to
deny the existence of a federal polity, of a national social compact, of a
nation.
206
This only made sense in the context of social contract theory and
what it implied about the Union: that there were two constitutions (one for
the polity and another for the government), the first of which necessarily
informed and shaped the second. Jefferson’s comments, in particular, are so
revealing and so rarely appreciated for what they imply. Republicans could
not concede, ultimately, that the federal Constitution was a constitution—it
had to be something else. If it was a constitution, if it spoke for a nation and
a national people, then all bets were off. Few developments more powerfully
underscore the nation’s importance—as a legal category at the founding—
202. JAMES MADISON, THE REPORT OF 1800 (Jan. 7, 1800), reprinted in 17 THE PAPERS OF
JAMES MADISON 303, 309 (David B. Mattern et al. eds., 1991). Though, in crucial ways,
Madison resisted compact theory. Unlike Jefferson and most other Republicans, he
acknowledged the existence of a national polity and national social contract; contrary to
nationalists, however, he believed that that polity did not predate the Constitution but rather
was only created through the act of ratifying it. See id. at 309, 315. While the states did not
retain sovereignty postratification, nonetheless they were the parties to the Constitution
because state polities had been the ones to divest the authority necessary to create the new
nation. See id. In a revealing development, John Marshall, despite his nationalism, would
make an argument similar to Madison’s some two decades later in defense of McCulloch v.
Maryland. See Martin S. Flaherty, John Marshall, McCulloch v. Maryland, and “We the
People”: Revisions in Need of Revising, 43 W
M. & MARY L. REV. 1339, 1370–79 (2002).
203. C
ORNELL, supra note 187, at 263–73.
204. On Tucker’s 1803 edition of Blackstone and how he attempted to republicanize it, see
Clyde N. Wilson, Foreword to S
T. GEORGE TUCKER, VIEW OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE
UNITED STATES, WITH SELECTED WRITINGS viii–x (Clyde N. Wilson ed., 1999).
205. S
T. GEORGE TUCKER, View of the Constitution of the United States (1803), reprinted
in V
IEW OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES, WITH SELECTED WRITINGS, supra note
204, at 91, 91–106.
206. See supra notes 194–96 and accompanying text.
2021] IN SEARCH OF NATIONHOOD AT THE FOUNDING 1813
than the emergence of compact theory. That Jeffersonians assumed, as a
matter of course, that their vision of limited constitutional power was
incompatible with the existence of a national polity confirms as much.
C
ONCLUSION
If we begin to understand why Federalists were so obsessed with
nationhood, and the creative constitutional thinking that grew out of that
obsession, we can bring back into focus a cluster of assumptions that were
once inseparable from efforts to interpret the Constitution. At the founding,
constitutional interpretation and social contract theory were often tightly
connected.
We are not beholden to anything Federalists or their opponents thought.
We need not assume, as they once did, that questions of constitutional
meaning and interpretation were inextricably entangled with questions of
sovereignty and union. Maybe, heeding Don Herzog’s recent advice, we will
decide that sovereignty is a concept that has outlived its usefulness.
207
Maybe, in our modern age, on the other side of positivist and historicist
revolutions that have fundamentally remade how we think about legal
authority and its fundamental basis, we will have little interest in social
contract theory and its attendant natural law assumptions. Maybe, especially
in the wake of the Civil War, we will decide it is tedious to sort out quasi-
metaphysical questions regarding the character of our federal polity and
instead be content with focusing on how the federal system works in practice
rather than theory. Maybe, in short, it just does not matter anymore whether,
constitutionally speaking, our polity was born a nation or a set of independent
states.
But what we cannot do is claim to be interested in recovering, describing,
or understanding the original Constitution, while ignoring the social contract
assumptions that Federalists and their opponents treated as foundational.
There is nothing wrong with reading the Constitution apart from any
particular understanding of federal union—times change, after all. But if the
point is to understand the Constitution as it once was—to recover the
meaning it might have had at its inception—then we need to appreciate what
reading the Constitution necessarily entailed. We cannot start with the
document or its words; we need to start with the Union for which it spoke.
Originally, the Constitution was inseparable from theories of federal union.
If we disaggregate one from the other, we do not clear the way for clearer
interpretation. To the contrary, we simply wrench the Constitution out of the
eighteenth century and transform it into something it originally was not. We
leave behind the past and make the Constitution an artifact of the present. If
then our goal is to confront the original Constitution on its own terms, we
need to understand why Federalists and, in turn, their opponents, cared so
deeply about the state of the nation.
207. See generally DON HERZOG, SOVEREIGNTY, R.I.P. (2020).